Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Seat Belt Mandates and Paternalism.Jessica Flanigan - 2017 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 14 (3):291-314.
    Seat belt mandates seem like a paradigmatic case of justified paternalism. Even those who generally object to paternalism often concede that seat belt laws are justified. Against this near-consensus in favor of mandates, I argue that seat belt laws are unjust and public officials should not enforce them. The most plausible exceptions to a principle of anti-paternalism do not justify seat belt mandates. Some argue that seat belt mandates are not paternalistic because unbelted riders are not fully autonomous. Others claim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (1 other version)Avoiding Paternalism.Peter de Marneffe - 2005 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (1):68-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Who Can Be Wronged?Rahul Kumar - 2003 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (2):99-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • Antipaternalism as a Filter on Reasons.Kalle Grill - 2015 - In Thomas Schramme (ed.), New Perspectives on Paternalism and Health Care. Cham: Springer Verlag.
    I first distinguish four types of objection to paternalism and argue that only one – the principled objection – amounts to a substantive and distinct normative doctrine. I then argue that this doctrine should be understood as preventing certain facts from playing the role of reasons they would otherwise play. I explain how this filter approach makes antipaternalism independent of several philosophical controversies: On the role reasons play, on what reasons there are, and on how reasons are related to values. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Abandoning the Abandonment Objection: Luck Egalitarian Arguments for Public Insurance.Carl Knight - 2015 - Res Publica 21 (2):119-135.
    Critics of luck egalitarianism have claimed that, far from providing a justification for the public insurance functions of a welfare state as its proponents claim, the view objectionably abandons those who are deemed responsible for their dire straits. This article considers seven arguments that can be made in response to this ‘abandonment objection’. Four of these arguments are found wanting, with a recurrent problem being their reliance on a dubious sufficientarian or quasi-sufficientarian commitment to provide a threshold of goods unconditionally. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Paternalism.John Kleinig - 1985 - Law and Philosophy 4 (1):115-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Harmless Wrongdoing.Joel Feinberg - 1990 - Oxford University Press.
    The final volume of Feinberg's four-volume work, The Moral Limits of Criminal Law examines the philosophical basis for the criminalization of so-called "victimless crimes" such as ticket scalping, blackmail, consented-to exploitation of others, commercial fortune telling, and consensual sexual relations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Harm to Self.Joel Feinberg - 1986 - Oxford University Press USA.
    This is the third volume of Joel Feinberg's highly regarded The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, a four-volume series in which Feinberg skillfully addresses a complex question: What kinds of conduct may the state make criminal without infringing on the moral autonomy of individual citizens? In Harm to Self, Feinberg offers insightful commentary into various notions attached to self-inflicted harm, covering such topics as legal paternalism, personal sovereignty and its boundaries, voluntariness and assumptions of risk, consent and its counterfeits, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • (1 other version)Paternalism.Gerald Dworkin - 1972 - The Monist 56 (1):64-84.
    I take as my starting point the “one very simple principle” proclaimed by Mill in On Liberty … “That principle is, that the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. He cannot rightfully be compelled to do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   296 citations  
  • The Non-Identity Problem and the Ethics of Future People.David Boonin - 2014 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    David Boonin presents a new account of the non-identity problem: a puzzle about our obligations to people who do not yet exist. He provides a critical survey of solutions to the problem that have been proposed, and concludes by developing an unorthodox alternative solution, one that differs fundamentally from virtually every other approach.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Paternalism and Personal Identity.John Kleinig - 2009 - Jahrbuch für Wissenschaft Und Ethik 14 (1):93-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of Harm.Seana Shiffrin - 1999 - Legal Theory 5 (2):117-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   217 citations  
  • Persons, Interests, and Justice.Nils Holtug - 2010 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    In our lives, we aim to achieve welfare for ourselves, that is, to live good lives. But we also have another, more impartial perspective, where we aim to balance our concern for our own welfare against a concern for the welfare of others. This is a perspective of justice. Nils Holtug examines these two perspectives and the relations between them.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Whose Body is It Anyway? Justice and the Integrity of the Person.Cécile Fabre - 2006 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Do we have the right to deny others access to our body? What if this would harm those who need personal services or body parts from us? Ccile Fabre examines the impact that arguments for distributive justice have on the rights we have over ourselves, and on such contentious issues as organ sales, prostitution, and surrogate motherhood.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Harm and the volenti principle.Gerald Dworkin - 2012 - Social Philosophy and Policy 29 (1):309-321.
    Research Articles Gerald Dworkin, Social Philosophy and Policy, FirstView Article.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Avoiding Paternalism.Peter De Marneffe - 2005 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (1):68 - 94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Legal Paternalism.Joel Feinberg - 1971 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1 (1):105 - 124.
    The principle of legal paternalism justifies state coercion to protect individuals from self-inflicted harm, or in its extreme version, to guide them, whether they like it or not, toward their own good. Parents can be expected to justify their interference in the lives of their children on the ground that “daddy knows best.” legal paternalism seems to imply that since the state often can know the interests of individual citizens better than the citizens know them themselves, it stands as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Compensation and transworld personal identity.George Sher - 1979 - The Monist 62 (3):378–91.
    A natural way of viewing compensation is to see it as the restoration of a good or level of well-being which someone would have enjoyed if he had not been adversely affected by the act of another. This view underlies Nozick’s assertion that “something fully compensates … person X for Y’s action A if X is no worse off receiving it, Y having done A, than X would have been without receiving it if Y had not done A”; and it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (1 other version)Equal Opportunity or Equal Social Outcome?Marc Fleurbaey - 1995 - Economics and Philosophy 11 (1):25.
    John Rawls's work has greatly contributed to rehabilitating equality as a basic social value, after decades of utilitarian hegemony,particularly in normative economics, but Rawls also emphasized that full equality of welfare is not an adequate goal either. This thesis was echoed in Dworkin's famous twin papers on equality, and it is now widely accepted that egalitarianism must be selective. The bulk of the debate on ‘Equality of What?’ thus deals with what variables ought to be submitted for selection and how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • A right of self‐termination?J. David Velleman - 1999 - Ethics 109 (3):606-628.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Advance directives and the personal identity problem.Allen Buchanan - 1988 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 17 (4):277-302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • What is the point of equality.Elizabeth Anderson - 1999 - Ethics 109 (2):287-337.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1011 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Later selves and moral principles.Derek Parfit - 1973 - In Alan Montefiore (ed.), Philosophy and personal relations. Montreal,: McGill- Queen's University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Reasons and Persons.Derek Parfit - 1984 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Challenging, with several powerful arguments, some of our deepest beliefs about rationality, morality, and personal identity, Parfit claims that we have a false view about our own nature. It is often rational to act against our own best interersts, he argues, and most of us have moral views that are self-defeating. We often act wrongly, although we know there will be no one with serious grounds for complaint, and when we consider future generations it is very hard to avoid conclusions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2869 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Later selves and moral principles.Derek Parfit - 1973 - In Alan Montefiore (ed.), Philosophy and Personal Relations: An Anglo-French Study. Montreal,: McGill-Queen's University Press. pp. 137-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Later Selves and Moral Principles.Derek Parfit - 1998 - In James Rachels (ed.), Ethical Theory 2: Theories About How We Should Live. Oxford University Press UK.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Should We Prevent Non‐Therapeutic Mutilation and Extreme Body Modification?Thomas Schramme - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (1):8-15.
    In this paper, I discuss several arguments against non‐therapeutic mutilation. Interventions into bodily integrity, which do not serve a therapeutic purpose and are not regarded as aesthetically acceptable by the majority, e.g. tongue splitting, branding and flesh stapling, are now practised, but, however, are still seen as a kind of ‘aberration’ that ought not to be allowed. I reject several arguments for a possible ban on these body modifications. I find the common pathologisation of body modifications, Kant's argument of duties (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On the Anti-paternalist Project of Reconciliation.Viki Møller Lyngby Pedersen - 2019 - Utilitas 31 (1):20-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Equal Opportunity, Responsibility, and Personal Identity.Ian Carter - 2018 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21 (4):825-839.
    According to the ‘starting-gate’ interpretation of equality of opportunity, individuals who enjoy equal starts can legitimately become unequal to the extent that their differences derive from choices for which they can be held responsible. There can be no coercive transfers of resources in favour of individuals who disregarded their own futures, and no limits on the right of an individual to distribute resources intrapersonally. This paper assesses two ways in which advocates of equality of opportunity might depart from the starting-gate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Slaves, gladiators, and death: Kantian liberalism and the moral limits of consent.Marc Ramsay - 2017 - Legal Theory 23 (2):96-131.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Paternalism and Right.Paul Schofield - 2017 - Journal of Political Philosophy 26 (1):65-83.
    Typically, we think of republicans and liberals as being suspicious of paternalistic law. But in this paper, I argue that enactment of paternalistic law is actually demanded by republican and liberal values, and that enacting certain paternalistic laws is one way that the republican or liberal state performs its core function. As I explain it, this core function is to create and to maintain conditions of right-conditions of freedom, non-domination, justice, etc.-among persons capable of making legitimate second-personal claims on one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Equal Opportunity or Equal Social Outcome?Marc Fleurbaey - 1994 - Economics and Philosophy 10 (2):25-55.
    John Rawls's work (1971) has greatly contributed to rehabilitating equality as a basic social value, after decades of utilitarian hegemony,particularly in normative economics, but Rawls also emphasized that full equality of welfare is not an adequate goal either. This thesis was echoed in Dworkin's famous twin papers on equality (Dworkin 1981a,b), and it is now widely accepted that egalitarianism must be selective. The bulk of the debate on ‘Equality of What?’ thus deals with what variables ought to be submitted for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Harm to Self.Joel Feinberg & Donald Vandeveer - 1988 - Ethics 98 (3):550-565.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • Toleration, harm, and moral effect.Peter Jones - 1985 - In John Horton & Susan Mendus (eds.), Aspects of toleration: philosophical studies. New York: Methuen.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Should we prevent non-therapeutic mutilation and extreme body modification?Thomas Schramme - 2007 - Bioethics 22 (1):8–15.
    ABSTRACT In this paper, I discuss several arguments against non‐therapeutic mutilation. Interventions into bodily integrity, which do not serve a therapeutic purpose and are not regarded as aesthetically acceptable by the majority, e.g. tongue splitting, branding and flesh stapling, are now practised, but, however, are still seen as a kind of ‘aberration’ that ought not to be allowed. I reject several arguments for a possible ban on these body modifications. I find the common pathologisation of body modifications, Kant's argument of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations