Switch to: Citations

References in:

Constructing copernicus

Perspectives on Science 10 (2):208-227 (2002)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The role of Rothmann in the dissolution of the celestial spheres.Bernard Goldstein & Peter Barker - 1995 - British Journal for the History of Science 28 (4):385-403.
    At the end of the sixteenth century astronomers and others felt compelled to choose among different cosmologies. For Tycho Brahe, who played a central role in these debates, the intersection of the spheres of Mars and the Sun was an outstanding problem that had to be resolved before he made his choice. His ultimate solution was to eliminate celestial spheres in favour of fluid heavens, a crucial step in the abandonment of the Ptolemaic system and the demise of Aristotelian celestial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Theory of Comets at Paris During the Seventeenth Century.Roger Ariew - 1992 - Journal of the History of Ideas 53 (3):355-372.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Patterns of discovery.Norwood Russell Hanson - 1958 - Cambridge [Eng.]: University Press.
    In this 1958 book, Professor Hanson turns to an equally important but comparatively neglected subject, the philosophical aspects of research and discovery.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   484 citations  
  • Distance and velocity in Kepler's astronomy.Peter Barker & Bernard R. Goldstein - 1994 - Annals of Science 51 (1):59-73.
    We will examine Kepler's use of a relation between velocity and distance from a centre of circular motion. This relation plays an essential role, through a derivation in chapter 40 of the Astronomia Nova, in the presentation of the Area Law of planetary motion. Kepler transcends ancient and contemporary applications of the distance-velocity relation by connecting it with his metaphysical commitment to the causal role of the Sun. His second main innovation is to replace the astronomical models of his predecessors (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Descartes' Metaphysical Physics.Daniel GARBER - 1992 - Studia Leibnitiana 26 (1):127-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • Tycho Brahe, Laboratory Design, and the Aim of Science: Reading Plans in Context.Jole Shackelford - 1993 - Isis 84:211-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Kepler's Philosophy and the New Astronomy.Rhonda Martens - 2000 - Princeton University Press.
    Here, Rhonda Martens offers the first extended study of Kepler's philosophical views and shows how those views helped him construct and justify the new astronomy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (1 other version)Jean Pena (1528-58) and stoic physics in the sixteenth century.Peter Barker - 1985 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (S1):93-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1957 - Harvard University Press.
    The significance of the plurality of the Copernican Revolution is the main thrust of this undergraduate text In this study of the Copernican Revolution, the ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   218 citations  
  • Realism and instrumentalism in sixteenth century astronomy: A reappraisal.Peter Barker & Bernard R. Goldstein - 1998 - Perspectives on Science 6 (3):232-258.
    : We question the claim, common since Duhem, that sixteenth century astronomy, and especially the Wittenberg interpretation of Copernicus, was instrumentalistic rather than realistic. We identify a previously unrecognized Wittenberg astronomer, Edo Hildericus (Hilderich von Varel), who presents a detailed exposition of Copernicus's cosmology that is incompatible with instrumentalism. Quotations from other sixteenth century astronomers show that knowledge of the real configuration of the heavens was unattainable practically, rather than in principle. Astronomy was limited to quia demonstrations, although demonstration propter (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The Transformation of Natural Philosophy. The Case of Philip Melanchthon.Sachiko Kusukawa - 1995
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • (1 other version)Two Cultures or One?: A Second Look at Kuhn's The Copernican Revolution.Robert S. Westman - 1994 - Isis 85 (1):79-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Is Seventeenth Century Physics Indebted to the Stoics?Peter Barker & Bernard R. Goldstein - 1984 - Centaurus 27 (2):148-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The Role of Comets in The Copernican Revolution.Peter Barker - 1988 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 19 (3):299.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Descartes and the last Scholastics.Roger Ariew - 1999 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    The volume touches upon many topics and themes shared by Cartesian and late scholastic philosophy: matter and form; infinity, place, time, void, and motion; the ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • (1 other version)Maestlin's Teaching of Copernicus: The Evidence of His University Textbook and Disputations.Charlotte Methuen - 1996 - Isis 87:230-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Two Cultures or One?: A Second Look at Kuhn's The Copernican Revolution.Robert Westman - 1994 - Isis 85:79-115.
    Thomas Kuhn's, book The Copernican Revolution deserves to be regarded as the best of that small group of longue duree histories that mark postwar historiography of science. In many respects, it is probably the single most influential one. Tightly written and brilliantly argued, it is responsible, together with The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, for the continued popularity of the metaphor of revolution in science among scholars and students alike. Yet, surprisingly, while aspects of the story conceived in Kuhn's original account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Copernicus, the orbs, and the equant.Peter Barker - 1990 - Synthese 83 (2):317 - 323.
    I argue that Copernicus accepted the reality of celestial spheres on the grounds that the equant problem is unintelligible except as a problem about real spheres. The same considerations point to a number of generally unnoticed liabilities of Copernican astronomy, especially gaps between the spheres, and the failure of some spheres to obey the principle that their natural motion is to rotate. These difficulties may be additional reasons for Copernicus's reluctance to publish, and also stand in the way of strict (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The role of religion in the Lutheran response to Copernicus.Peter Barker - 2000 - In Margaret J. Osler (ed.), Rethinking the Scientific Revolution. Cambridge University Press. pp. 59--88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations