Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Fixed points and unfounded chains.Claudio Bernardi - 2001 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 109 (3):163-178.
    By an unfounded chain for a function f:X→X we mean a sequence nω of elements of X s.t. fxn+1=xn for every n. Unfounded chains can be regarded as a generalization of fixed points, but on the other hand are linked with concepts concerning non-well-founded situations, as ungrounded sentences and the hypergame. In this paper, among other things, we prove a lemma in general topology, we exhibit an extensional recursive function from the set of sentences of PA into itself without an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Paradox without Self-Reference.Stephen Yablo - 1993 - Analysis 53 (4):251-252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   205 citations  
  • Yablo's paradox.Graham Priest - 1997 - Analysis 57 (4):236-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • What Truth Depends on.Hannes Leitgeb - 2005 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (2):155-192.
    What kinds of sentences with truth predicate may be inserted plausibly and consistently into the T-scheme? We state an answer in terms of dependence: those sentences which depend directly or indirectly on non-semantic states of affairs (only). In order to make this precise we introduce a theory of dependence according to which a sentence φ is said to depend on a set Φ of sentences iff the truth value of φ supervenes on the presence or absence of the sentences of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Truth and reflection.Stephen Yablo - 1985 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 14 (3):297 - 349.
    Many topics have not been covered, in most cases because I don't know quite what to say about them. Would it be possible to add a decidability predicate to the language? What about stronger connectives, like exclusion negation or Lukasiewicz implication? Would an expanded language do better at expressing its own semantics? Would it contain new and more terrible paradoxes? Can the account be supplemented with a workable notion of inherent truth (see note 36)? In what sense does stage semantics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • The Elimination of Self-Reference: Generalized Yablo-Series and the Theory of Truth.P. Schlenker - 2007 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 36 (3):251-307.
    Although it was traditionally thought that self-reference is a crucial ingredient of semantic paradoxes, Yablo (1993, 2004) showed that this was not so by displaying an infinite series of sentences none of which is self-referential but which, taken together, are paradoxical. Yablo's paradox consists of a countable series of linearly ordered sentences s(0), s(1), s(2),... , where each s(i) says: For each k > i, s(k) is false (or equivalently: For no k > i is s(k) true). We generalize Yablo's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Yablo’s Paradox and ω-Inconsistency.Jeffrey Ketland - 2005 - Synthese 145 (3):295-302.
    It is argued that Yablo’s Paradox is not strictly paradoxical, but rather ‘ω-paradoxical’. Under a natural formalization, the list of Yablo sentences may be constructed using a diagonalization argument and can be shown to be ω-inconsistent, but nonetheless consistent. The derivation of an inconsistency requires a uniform fixed-point construction. Moreover, the truth-theoretic disquotational principle required is also uniform, rather than the local disquotational T-scheme. The theory with the local disquotation T-scheme applied to individual sentences from the Yablo list is also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Translating the hypergame paradox: Remarks on the set of founded elements of a relation. [REVIEW]Claudio Bernardi & Giovanna D'Agostino - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 (5):545 - 557.
    In Zwicker (1987) the hypergame paradox is introduced and studied. In this paper we continue this investigation, comparing the hypergame argument with the diagonal one, in order to find a proof schema. In particular, in Theorems 9 and 10 we discuss the complexity of the set of founded elements in a recursively enumerable relation on the set N of natural numbers, in the framework of reduction between relations. We also find an application in the theory of diagonalizable algebras and construct (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A yabloesque paradox in set theory.Laurence Goldstein - 1994 - Analysis 54 (4):223-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Paradox of the class of all grounded classes.Shen Yuting - 1953 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 (2):114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Patterns of paradox.Roy T. Cook - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (3):767-774.
    We begin with a prepositional languageLpcontaining conjunction (Λ), a class of sentence names {Sα}αϵA, and a falsity predicateF. We (only) allow unrestricted infinite conjunctions, i.e., given any non-empty class of sentence names {Sβ}βϵB,is a well-formed formula (we will useWFFto denote the set of well-formed formulae).The language, as it stands, is unproblematic. Whether various paradoxes are produced depends on which names are assigned to which sentences. What is needed is a denotation function:For example, theLPsentence “F(S1)” (i.e.,Λ{F(S1)}), combined with a denotation functionδsuch (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Descending Chains and the Contextualist Approach to Semantic Paradoxes.Byeong-Uk Yi - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (4):554-567.
    Plausible principles on truth seem to yield contradictory conclusions about paradoxical sentences such as the Strengthened Liar. Those who take the contextualist approach, such as Parsons and Burge, attempt to justify the seemingly contradictory conclusions by arguing that the natural reasoning that leads to them involves some kind of contextual shift that makes them compatible. This paper argues that one cannot take this approach to give a proper treatment of infinite descending chains of semantic attributions. It also examines a related (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations