Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Teleology then and now: The question of Kant’s relevance for contemporary controversies over function in biology.John Zammito - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):748-770.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • De constructie van het verleden: een inleiding in de theorie van de geschiedenis.Chris Lorenz - 1987 - Boom Koninklijke Uitgevers.
    Studie over een aantal wetenschapsfilosofische problemen waarmee de geschiedbeoefening wordt geconfronteerd.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Unit-ideas Unleashed: A Reinterpretation and Reassessment of Lovejovian Methodology in the History of Ideas.Carl Knight - 2012 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 6 (2):195-217.
    This article argues for an unconventional interpretation of Arthur O. Lovejoy’s distinctive approach to method in the history of ideas. It is maintained that the value of the central concept of the ‘unit-idea’ has been misunderstood by friends and foes alike. The commonality of unit-ideas at different times and places is often defined in terms of familial resemblance. But such an approach must necessarily define unit-ideas as being something other than the smallest conceptual unit. It is therefore in tension with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Similarity After Goodman.Lieven Decock & Igor Douven - 2011 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2 (1):61-75.
    In a famous critique, Goodman dismissed similarity as a slippery and both philosophically and scientifically useless notion. We revisit his critique in the light of important recent work on similarity in psychology and cognitive science. Specifically, we use Tversky’s influential set-theoretic account of similarity as well as Gärdenfors’s more recent resuscitation of the geometrical account to show that, while Goodman’s critique contained valuable insights, it does not warrant a dismissal of similarity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • The Logic of the History of Ideas.Mark Bevir - 1999 - Cambridge University Press.
    This paper provides a short summary of Mark Bevir, The Logic of the History of Ideas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999). Logic stands here as a subset of Wittgenstein’s notion of philosophy as a matter of the grammar of our concepts. It studies the forms of reasoning appropriate to a discipline, rather than the material of that discipline. Hence, the logic of the history of ideas considers the nature of meaning, the way we should justify our knowledge of past meanings, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea.Arthur O. Lovejoy - 1936 - Cambridge, Mass.,: Transaction Publishers.
    This is arguably the seminal work in historical andphilosophical analysis of the twentieth century.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • The classical model of science: A millennia-old model of scientific rationality.Willem R. de Jong & Arianna Betti - 2010 - Synthese 174 (2):185-203.
    Throughout more than two millennia philosophers adhered massively to ideal standards of scientific rationality going back ultimately to Aristotle’s Analytica posteriora . These standards got progressively shaped by and adapted to new scientific needs and tendencies. Nevertheless, a core of conditions capturing the fundamentals of what a proper science should look like remained remarkably constant all along. Call this cluster of conditions the Classical Model of Science . In this paper we will do two things. First of all, we will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Lovejoy's The Great Chain of Being after Fifty Years.Daniel J. Wilson - 1987 - Journal of the History of Ideas 48 (2):187.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Geistesgeschichte vs. History of Ideas as Applied to Hitlerism.Leo Spitzer - 1944 - Journal of the History of Ideas 5 (1/4):191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The History of Ideas, Intellectual History, and the History of Philosophy.Maurice Mandelbaum - 1965 - History and Theory 5:33.
    The history of ideas deals with the elemental unit-ideas which for Lovejoy are components of systems distinguished by their patterns. Special histories explain how a particular form of human history developed. General histories draw on special histories to document or explain social contexts. Since patterns influence philosophers, the history of ideas contributes little to the history of philosophy, a discontinuous strand within a period's continuous intellectual history. By accepting cultural pluralism, denying the monistic position that there always are internal connections (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Reply to Professor Spitzer.Arthur O. Lovejoy - 1944 - Journal of the History of Ideas 5 (1/4):204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reflections on the History of Ideas.Arthur O. Lovejoy - 1940 - Journal of the History of Ideas 1 (1/4):3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The Foundations of Mathematics a Study in the Philosophy of Science.Evert Willem Beth - 1959 - Amsterdam, Netherlands: Harper & Row.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Making sense of conceptual change.Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen - 2008 - History and Theory 47 (3):351-372.
    Arthur Lovejoy’s history of unit-ideas and the history of concepts are often criticized for being historically insensitive forms of history-writing. Critics claim that one cannot find invariable ideas or concepts in several contexts or times in history without resorting to some distortion. One popular reaction is to reject the history of ideas and concepts altogether, and take linguistic entities as the main theoretical units. Another reaction is to try to make ideas or concepts context-sensitive and to see their histories as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (1 other version)Teleology then and now: The question of Kant's relevance for contemporary controversies over function in biology.John Zammito - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):748-770.
    Kant -- drawing on his eighteenth-century predecessors -- provided a discerning and powerful characterization of what biologists had to explain in organic form. His difference from the rest is that he opined that was impossible to explain it. Its ’inscrutability’ was intrinsic. The third ’Critique’ essentially proposed the reduction of biology to a kind of prescientific descriptivism, doomed never to attain authentic scientificity. By contrast, for Locke, and ’a fortiori’ for Buffon and his followers, ’intrinsic purposiveness’ was a fact of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • (1 other version)The analytic-synthetic distinction and the classical model of science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege.Willem R. De Jong - 2010 - Synthese 174 (2):237 - 261.
    This paper concentrates on some aspects of the history of the analyticsynthetic distinction from Kant to Bolzano and Frege. This history evinces considerable continuity but also some important discontinuities. The analytic-synthetic distinction has to be seen in the first place in relation to a science, i.e. an ordered system of cognition. Looking especially to the place and role of logic it will be argued that Kant, Bolzano and Frege each developed the analytic-synthetic distinction within the same conception of scientific rationality, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Gaps in the Great Chain of Being: An Exercise in the Methodology of the History of Ideas.Jaakko Hintikka - 1975 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 49:22 - 38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Perils of Plenitude: Hintikka contra Lovejoy.Moltke S. Gram - 1980 - Journal of the History of Ideas 41 (3):497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Visions of politics.Quentin Skinner - 2002 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The first of three volumes of essays by Quentin Skinner, one of the world's leading intellectual historians. This collection includes some of his most important philosophical and methodological statements written over the past four decades, each carefully revised for publication in this form. In a series of seminal essays Professor Skinner sets forth the intellectual principles that inform his work. Writing as a practising historian, he considers the theoretical difficulties inherent in the pursuit of knowledge and interpretation, and elucidates the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • (1 other version)The analytic-synthetic distinction and the classical model of science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege.Willem R. de Jong - 2010 - Synthese 174 (2):237-261.
    This paper concentrates on some aspects of the history of the analytic-synthetic distinction from Kant to Bolzano and Frege. This history evinces considerable continuity but also some important discontinuities. The analytic-synthetic distinction has to be seen in the first place in relation to a science, i.e. an ordered system of cognition. Looking especially to the place and role of logic it will be argued that Kant, Bolzano and Frege each developed the analytic-synthetic distinction within the same conception of scientific rationality, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Bernard Bolzano, analyticity and the aristotelian model of science.Willem R. de Jong - 2001 - Kant Studien 92 (3):328-349.
    Quine's well-known ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’ (1951) plays a key role in the debate about the analytic-synthetic distinction. Taking to task the ideas of Carnap in particular, Quine shows that logical positivism works with a concept of scientific rationality that is based dogmatically on, among other things, the opposition analytic-synthetic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Kuhn's account of family resemblance: A solution to the problem of wide-open texture.Hanne Andersen - 2000 - Erkenntnis 52 (3):313-337.
    It is a commonly raised argument against the family resemblance account of concepts that there is no limit to a concept's extension. An account of family resemblance which attempts to provide a solution to this problem by including both similarity among instances and dissimilarity to non-instances has been developed by the philosopher of science Thomas Kuhn. Similar solutions have been hinted at in the literature on family resemblance concepts, but the solution has never received a detailed investigation. I shall provide (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Romantic Conception of Life: Science and Philosophy in the Age of Goethe.Robert J. Richards - 2002 - University of Chicago Press.
    "All art should become science and all science art; poetry and philosophy should be made one." Friedrich Schlegel's words perfectly capture the project of the German Romantics, who believed that the aesthetic approaches of art and literature could reveal patterns and meaning in nature that couldn't be uncovered through rationalistic philosophy and science alone. In this wide-ranging work, Robert J. Richards shows how the Romantic conception of the world influenced (and was influenced by) both the lives of the people who (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   116 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Logic of the History of Ideas.Mark Bevir - 2001 - Mind 110 (437):163-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Logic of the History of Ideas.Mark Bevir - 2000 - Philosophical Quarterly 50 (200):407-409.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Great Chain of Being. A Study of the History of an Idea.A. O. Lovejoy - 1937 - Philosophy 12 (45):113-114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • On Method in the History of Ideas.Nils Bjorn Kvastad - 1978 - International Logic Review 1718:96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations