Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Accountable to Whom? Rethinking the Role of Corporations in Political CSR.Waheed Hussain & Jeffrey Moriarty - 2018 - Journal of Business Ethics 149 (3):519-534.
    According to Palazzo and Scherer, the changing role of business corporations in society requires that we take new measures to integrate these organizations into society-wide processes of democratic governance. We argue that their model of integration has a fundamental problem. Instead of treating business corporations as agents that must be held accountable to the democratic reasoning of affected parties, it treats corporations as agents who can hold others accountable. In our terminology, it treats business corporations as “supervising authorities” rather than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Mandatory Vaccination: An Unqualified Defence.Roland Pierik - 2018 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 35 (2):381-398.
    The 2015 Disneyland outbreak of measles in the US unequivocally brought to light what had been brewing below the surface for a while: a slow but steady decline in vaccination rates resulting in a rising number of outbreaks. This can be traced back to an increasing public questioning of vaccines by an emerging anti-vaccination movement. This article argues that, in the face of diminishing vaccination rates, childhood vaccinations should not be seen as part of the domain of parental choice but, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • (1 other version)Culture and Equality: An Egalitarian Critique of Multiculturalism.Brian Barry - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (210):152-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Multicultural Citizenship: a Liberal Theory of Minority Rights.Will Kymlicka - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (187):250-253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   282 citations  
  • The Institutional Division of Labor and the Egalitarian Obligations of Nonprofits.Chiara Cordelli - 2012 - Journal of Political Philosophy 20 (2):131-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Rawlsian View of Private Ordering.Kevin A. Kordana - 2008 - Social Philosophy and Policy 25 (2):288-307.
    The Rawlsian texts appear not to be consistent with regard to the status of the right of freedom of association. Interestingly, Rawls's early work omits mention of freedom of association as among the basic liberties, but in his later work he explicitly includes freedom of association as among the basic liberties. However, freedom of association would appear to have an economic component as well (e.g., the right to form a firm). If one turns to such “private ordering” (e.g., contract, partnership, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Corporate Institutions in a Weakened Welfare State: A Rawlsian Perspective.Sandrine Blanc & Ismael Al-Amoudi - 2013 - Business Ethics Quarterly 23 (4):497-525.
    ABSTRACT:This paper re-examines the import of Rawls’s theory of justice for private sector institutions in the face of the decline of the welfare state. The argument is based on a Rawlsian conception of justice as the establishment of a basic structure of society that guarantees a fair distribution of primary goods. We propose that the decline of the welfare state witnessed in Western countries over the past forty years prompts a reassessment of the boundaries of the basic structure in order (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Rethinking the Very Idea of Egalitarian Markets and Corporations: Why Relationships Might Matter More than Distribution.Pierre-Yves Néron - 2015 - Business Ethics Quarterly 25 (1):93-124.
    ABSTRACT: What kinds of markets, market regulations, and business organizations are compatible with contemporary egalitarian theories of justice? This article argues that any thoughtful answer to this question will have to draw on recent developments in political philosophy that are concerned not only with the equality of the distribution of core goods but also with the requirements for equality of status, voice, and so on, in the relations between individuals and within organizations. The dominance of theories of distributive justice in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • (1 other version)Religious Exemptions: An Egalitarian Demand?Stuart G. White - 2012 - The Law and Ethics of Human Rights 6 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Goods of Work (Other Than Money!).Anca Gheaus & Lisa Herzog - 2016 - Journal of Social Philosophy 47 (1):70-89.
    The evaluation of labour markets and of particular jobs ought to be sensitive to a plurality of benefits and burdens of work. We use the term 'the goods of work' to refer to those benefits of work that cannot be obtained in exchange for money and that can be enjoyed mostly or exclusively in the context of work. Drawing on empirical research and various philosophical traditions of thinking about work we identify four goods of work: 1) attaining various types of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Distributive Justice, the Basic Structure and the Place of Private Law.Samuel Scheffler - 2015 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 35 (2):213-235.
    In John Rawls’s theory, the role of the principles of justice is to regulate the basic structure of society—its major social, political and economic institutions—and to specify the fair terms of cooperation for free and equal persons. Some have interpreted Rawls as excluding contract law, and perhaps the private law as a whole, from the basic structure. However, this interpretation of Rawls is untenable, given the motivations for his emphasis on the basic structure and the highly inclusive characterisations he gives (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Chapter One. On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice.G. A. H. G. Cohen - 2011 - In G. A. Cohen (ed.), On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice, and Other Essays in Political Philosophy. Princeton University Press. pp. 3-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Rights, Equality and Procreation.Paula Casal & Andrew Williams - 1995 - Analyse & Kritik 17 (1):93-116.
    Individual decisions about how to exercise the legal right to procreative liberty may generate either positive or negative externalities. From within a resource egalitarian perspective, such as that of Ronald Dworkin, it can be argued that procreative justice is asymmetric in the following respect. Justice need not require that parents be subsidised if they produce a public good, yet its ideal achievement may require their activities be taxed if they threaten to produce a public bad.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Consent, contestability and employer authority.Lars Lindblom - 2009 - Revue de Philosophie Économique 2 (2):47-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Les fondements égalitaristes des pratiques d'accommodement de la diversité religieuse.François Boucher - 2011 - Revue Philosophique De Louvain 109 (4):671-695.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Religious Exemptions: An Egalitarian Demand?Stuart G. White - 2012 - Law and Ethics of Human Rights 6 (1):97-118.
    To what extent does the case for exemptions from laws to accommodate religious commitments rest specifically on egalitarian arguments? To what extent should specifically egalitarian or anti-discrimination concerns be used to determine when such exemptions should be granted? This Article considers both of these questions. It argues that while egalitarian considerations have a role to play in both the general justification and case-by-case evaluation of exemption claims, neither the justification, nor the evaluation of exemptions, properly rests solely on specifically egalitarian (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Children as Public Goods?Serena Olsaretti - 2013 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 41 (3):226-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Three Rawlsian Routes towards Economic Democracy.Martin O'Neill - 2008 - Revue de Philosophie Économique 9 (1):29-55.
    This paper addresses ways of arguing fors ome form of economic democracy from within a broadly Rawlsian framework. Firstly, one can argue that a right to participate in economic decision-making should be added to the Rawlsian list of basic liberties, protected by the first principle of justice. Secondly,I argue that a society which institutes forms of economic democracy will be more likely to preserve a stable and just basic structure over time, by virtue of the effects of economic democratization on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • When should conscientious objection be accepted.Morten Magelssen - 2012 - Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (1):18-21.
    This paper makes two main claims: first, that the need to protect health professionals' moral integrity is what grounds the right to conscientious objection in health care; and second, that for a given claim of conscientious objection to be acceptable to society, a certain set of criteria should be fulfilled. The importance of moral integrity for individuals and society, including its special role in health care, is advocated. Criteria for evaluating the acceptability of claims to conscientious objection are outlined. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Rawlsian Justice and Workplace Republicanism.Nien-hê Hsieh - 2005 - Social Theory and Practice 31 (1):115-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Rawls, Self-Respect, and the Opportunity for Meaningful Work.Jeffrey Moriarty - 2009 - Social Theory and Practice 35 (3):441-459.
    John Rawls says that one of the requirements for stability is “[s]ociety as an employer of last resort” (PLP, lix). He explains: “[t]he lack of . . . the opportunity for meaningful work and occupation is destructive . . . of citizens’ self-respect” (PLP, lix). Rawls implies in these claims that the opportunity for meaningful work is a social basis of self-respect. This constitutes a significant shift in his account of self-respect, one that has been overlooked. I begin by clarifying (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Historical Emissions and Free-Riding.Axel Gosseries - 2004 - Ethical Perspectives 11 (1):36-60.
    Should the current members of a community compensate the victims of their ancestor’s emissions of greenhouse gases? I argue that the previous generation of polluters may not have been morally responsible for the harms they caused.I also accept the view that the polluters’ descendants cannot be morally responsible for their ancestor’s harmful emissions. However, I show that, while granting this, a suitably defined notion of moral free-riding may still account for the moral obligation of the polluters’ descendants to compensate the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • The Ethical Limitations of the Market.Elizabeth Anderson - 1990 - Economics and Philosophy 6 (2):179.
    A distinctive feature of modern capitalist societies is the tendency of the market to take over the production, maintenance, and distribution of goods that were previously produced, maintained, and distributed by nonmarket means. Yet, there is a wide range of disagreement regarding the proper extent of the market in providing many goods. Labor has been treated as a commodity since the advent of capitalism, but not without significant and continuing challenges to this arrangement. Other goods whose production for and distribution (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • The most stable just regime.Waheed Hussain - 2009 - Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (3):412-433.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Taxation, the private law, and distributive justice.Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick - 2006 - Social Philosophy and Policy 23 (2):142-165.
    We argue that for theorists with a post-institutional conception of property, e.g., Rawlsians, there is no principled reason to limit the domain of distributive justice to tax and transfer-both tax policy and the rules of the private law are constructed in service to distributive aims. Such theorists cannot maintain a commitment to a normative conception of private law independent of their overarching distributive principles. In contrast, theorists with a pre-institutional conception of property can derive the private law from sectors of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Justice as fairness.John Rawls - 1958 - Philosophical Review 67 (2):164-194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   332 citations  
  • Cultural exemptions, expensive tastes, and equal opportunities.Jonathan Quong - 2006 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 23 (1):53–71.
    abstract The most well‐known liberal‐egalitarian defence of cultural rights, provided by Will Kymlicka, presents culture as a primary good, and thus a resource that ought to be distributed according to some fair egalitarian criteria. Kymlicka relies on the intuition that inequalities between persons that are the result of brute luck rather than personal choice are unjust in making the case for various multicultural rights. This article makes two main claims. First, the standard luck egalitarian intuition on which Kymlicka's argument relies (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Are there any natural rights?Herbert Hart - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (2):175-191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   418 citations  
  • Rawls' system of justice: A critique from the left.Gerald Doppelt - 1981 - Noûs 15 (3):259-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Conscientious objection.Carl Cohen - 1968 - Ethics 78 (4):269-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition.John Rawls - 1999 - Harvard University Press.
    Previous edition, 1st, published in 1971.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1821 citations  
  • Firms and parental justice: should firms contribute to the cost of parenthood and procreation?Sandrine Blanc & Tim Meijers - 2020 - Economics and Philosophy 36 (1):1-27.
    This article asks whether firms should contribute to the costs of procreation and parenthood. We explore two sets of arguments. First, we ask what the principle of fair play – central in parental justice debates – implies. We argue that if one defends a pro-sharing view, firms are required to shoulder part of the costs of procreation and parenthood. Second, we turn to the principle of fair equality of opportunity. We argue that compensating firms for costs they incur because their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations