Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Principles of biomedical ethics.Tom L. Beauchamp - 1983 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by James F. Childress.
    Over the course of its first seven editions, Principles of Biomedical Ethics has proved to be, globally, the most widely used, authored work in biomedical ethics. It is unique in being a book in bioethics used in numerous disciplines for purposes of instruction in bioethics. Its framework of moral principles is authoritative for many professional associations and biomedical institutions-for instruction in both clinical ethics and research ethics. It has been widely used in several disciplines for purposes of teaching in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1940 citations  
  • The concept of precedent autonomy.John K. Davies - 2002 - Bioethics 16 (2):114–133.
    Does respect for autonomy imply respect for precedent autonomy? The principle of respect for autonomy requires us to respect a competent patient’s treatment preference, but not everyone agrees that it requires us to respect preferences formed earlier by a now‐incapacitated patient, such as those expressed in an advance directive. The concept of precedent autonomy, which concerns just such preferences, is problematic because it is not clear that we can still attribute to a now‐incapacitated patient a preference which that patient never (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Choosing for Others as Continuing a Life Story: The Problem of Personal Identity Revisited.Jeffrey Blustein - 1999 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27 (1):20-31.
    Philosophically, the most interesting objection to the reliance on advance directives to guide treatment decisions for formerly competent patients is the argument from the loss of personal identity. Starting with a psychological continuity theory of personal identity, the argument concludes that the very conditions that bring an advance directive into play may destroy the conditions necessary for personal identity, and so undercut the authority of the directive. In this article, I concede that if the purpose of a theory of personal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Choosing for others as Continuing a Life Story: The Problem of Personal Identity Revisited.Jeffrey Blustein - 1999 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27 (1):20-31.
    Philosophically, the most interesting objection to the reliance on advance directives to guide treatment decisions for formerly competent patients is the argument from the loss of personal identity. Starting with a psychological continuity theory of personal identity, the argument concludes that the very conditions that bring an advance directive into play may destroy the conditions necessary for personal identity, and so undercut the authority of the directive. In this article, I concede that if the purpose of a theory of personal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • On Taking Substituted Judgment Seriously.Charles Baron - 1990 - Hastings Center Report 20 (5):7-8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Interpreting surrogate consent using counterfactuals.Deborah Barnbaum - 1999 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 16 (2):167–172.
    Philosophers such as Dan Brock believe that surrogates who make health care decisions on behalf of previously competent patients, in the absence of an advance directive, should make these decisions based upon a substituted judgment principle. Brock favours substituted judgment over a best interests standard. However, Edward Wierenga claims that the substituted judgment principle ought to be abandoned in favour of a best interests standard, because of an inherent problem with the substituted judgment principle. Wierenga's version of the substituted judgment (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Decision Making in Health Care: limitations of the substituted judgement principle.Susan Bailey - 2002 - Nursing Ethics 9 (5):483-493.
    The substituted judgement principle is often recommended as a means of promoting the self-determination of an incompetent individual when proxy decision makers are faced with having to make decisions about health care. This article represents a critical ethical analysis of this decision-making principle and describes practical impediments that serve to undermine its fundamental purpose. These impediments predominantly stem from the informality associated with the application of the substituted judgement principle. It is recommended that the principles upon which decisions are made (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Revising the Substituted Judgment Standard.Ralph Baergen - 1995 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 6 (1):30-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Proxy consent and counterfactual wishes.Edward Wierenga - 1983 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 8 (4):405-416.
    I discuss conditions for the validity of proxy consent to treatment on behalf of an incompetent person. I distinguish those incompetents who, when previously competent, expressed an opinion on the treatment in question from those who were never competent or who, though previously competent, never expressed an opinion on the proposed treatment. In the former case valid proxy consent usually requires respecting the stated wishes of the patient. The latter case is more difficult. I consider a widely-held principle which appeals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Paternalistic Intervention: The Moral Bounds on Benevolence.Donald Vandeveer - 1986 - Princeton University Press.
    Donald VanDeVeer probes the moral complexities of the question: under what conditions is it permissible to intervene invasively in the lives of competent persons--for example, by deception, force, or coercive threat--for their own good? In a work with broad significance for law, public policy, professional-client relations, and private interactions, he presents a theory of an autonomy-respecting" paternalism. Originally published in 1986. The Princeton Legacy Library uses the latest print-on-demand technology to again make available previously out-of-print books from the distinguished backlist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Do Physicians’ Own Preferences for Life-Sustaining Treatment Influence Their Perceptions of Patients’ Preferences?Lawrence J. Schneiderman, Robert M. Kaplan, Robert A. Pearlman & Holly Teetzel - 1993 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 4 (1):28-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Legal and Functional Status of the Medical Proxy: Suggestions for Statutory Reform.Charles P. Sabatino - 1999 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27 (1):52-68.
    Medical technology, specialization, and the corporatization of health delivery systems in the late twentieth century have all helped give birth to an unwelcome but unavoidable responsibility for individuals with family or friends—serving as a health care proxy. The responsibility comes without monetary compensation, is often involuntary, and lacks any real guidelines beyond the duty to make life-and-death decisions in circumstances over which the proxy has little control.The parameters of the proxy's job have evolved somewhat awkwardly in statutes and case law, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Legal and Functional Status of the Medical Proxy: Suggestions for Statutory Reform.Charles P. Sabatino - 1999 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27 (1):52-68.
    Medical technology, specialization, and the corporatization of health delivery systems in the late twentieth century have all helped give birth to an unwelcome but unavoidable responsibility for individuals with family or friends—serving as a health care proxy. The responsibility comes without monetary compensation, is often involuntary, and lacks any real guidelines beyond the duty to make life-and-death decisions in circumstances over which the proxy has little control.The parameters of the proxy's job have evolved somewhat awkwardly in statutes and case law, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Autonomy, Benevolence, and Alzheimer's Disease.Pam R. Sailors - 2001 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 10 (2):184-193.
    Medical ethics has traditionally been governed by two guiding, but sometimes conflicting, principlesthe Substituted Judgment Standard shows our concern for autonomy, whereas the Best Interest Standard shows our commitment to benevolence. Both standards are vulnerable to criticisms. Further, the principles can seem to offer conflicting prescriptions for action. The criticisms and conflict figure prominently in discussion of advance directive decisionmaking and Alzheimer's disease. After laying out each of the current standards and its problems, with Alzheimer's issues as my central concern, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Living wills and substituted judgments: A critical analysis.Jos V. M. Welie - 2001 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 4 (2):169-183.
    In the literature three mechanisms are commonly distinguished to make decisions about the care of incompetent patients: A living will, a substituted judgment by a surrogate (who may or may not hold the power of attorney ), and a best interest judgment. Almost universally, the third mechanism is deemed the worst possible of the three, to be invoked only when the former two are unavailable. In this article, I argue in favor of best interest judgments. The evermore common aversion of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Is There a Duty to Die?John Hardwig - 1997 - Hastings Center Report 27 (2):34-42.
    When Richard Lamm made the statement that old people have a duty to die, it was generally shouted down or ridiculed. The whole idea is just too preposterous to entertain. Or too threatening. In fact, a fairly common argument against legalizing physician-assisted suicide is that if it were legal, some people might somehow get the idea that they have a duty to die. These people could only be the victims of twisted moral reasoning or vicious social pressure. It goes without (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Deciding for Others.Gerald Dworkin, Allen E. Buchanan & Dan W. Brock - 1991 - Philosophical Quarterly 41 (162):118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Encyclopedia of Bioethics, 3rd edition.Stephen G. Post (ed.) - 2004 - MacMillan Reference USA.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Deciding for Others: The Ethics of Surrogate Decision Making.Allen E. Buchanan & Dan W. Brock - 1989 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Dan W. Brock.
    This book is the most comprehensive treatment available of one of the most urgent - and yet in some respects most neglected - problems in bioethics: decision-making for incompetents. Part I develops a general theory for making treatment and care decisions for patients who are not competent to decide for themselves. It provides an in-depth analysis of competence, articulates and defends a coherent set of principles to specify suitable surrogate decisionmakers and to guide their choices, examines the value of advance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   258 citations  
  • Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?R. Eugene Bales - 1971 - American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (3):257 - 265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations