Switch to: Citations

References in:

What is an omission?

Philosophical Issues 22 (1):127-143 (2012)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility.John Martin Fischer & Mark Ravizza - 1998 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Mark Ravizza.
    This book provides a comprehensive, systematic theory of moral responsibility. The authors explore the conditions under which individuals are morally responsible for actions, omissions, consequences, and emotions. The leading idea in the book is that moral responsibility is based on 'guidance control'. This control has two components: the mechanism that issues in the relevant behavior must be the agent's own mechanism, and it must be appropriately responsive to reasons. The book develops an account of both components. The authors go on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   804 citations  
  • und Hintikka, M.B. Vermazen - 1985 - In Bruce Vermazen & Merrill B. Hintikka (eds.), Essays on Davidson: actions and events. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Killing and Letting Die.O. H. Green - 1980 - American Philosophical Quarterly 17 (3):195 - 204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Omissions, Responsibility, and Symmetry.Randolph Clarke - 2011 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82 (3):594-624.
    It is widely held that one can be responsible for doing something that one was unable to avoid doing. This paper focuses primarily on the question of whether one can be responsible for not doing something that one was unable to do. The paper begins with an examination of the account of responsibility for omissions offered by John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza, arguing that in many cases it yields mistaken verdicts. An alternative account is sketched that jibes with and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Norm and action.Georg Henrik von Wright - 1963 - New York,: Humanities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  • Causation and Counterfactuals.John Collins, Ned Hall & Laurie Paul (eds.) - 2004 - MIT Press.
    Thirty years after Lewis's paper, this book brings together some of the most important recent work connecting—or, in some cases, disputing the connection ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   157 citations  
  • (1 other version)Intention.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1957 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    This is a welcome reprint of a book that continues to grow in importance.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   883 citations  
  • (1 other version)The moral limits of the criminal law.Joel Feinberg - 1984 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this volume, Feinberg focuses on the meanings of "interest," the relationship between interests and wants, and the distinction between want-regarding and ideal-regarding analyses on interest and hard cases for the applications of the concept of harm. Examples of the "hard cases" are harm to character, vicarious harm, and prenatal and posthumous harm. Feinberg also discusses the relationship between harm and rights, the concept of a victim, and the distinctions of various quantitative dimensions of harm, consent, and offense, including the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Void and Object.David K. Lewis - 2004 - In John Collins, Ned Hall & Laurie Paul (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals. MIT Press. pp. 277-290.
    The void is deadly. If you were cast into a void, it would cause you to die in just a few minutes. It would suck the air from your lungs. It would boil your blood. It would drain the warmth from your body. And it would inflate enclosures in your body until they burst}.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • The Talk I Was Supposed to Give….Achille C. Varzi - 2006 - In Andrea Bottani & Richard Davies (eds.), Modes of Existence: Papers in Ontology and Philosophical Logic. Ontos Verlag. pp. 131–152.
    Assuming that events form a genuine ontological category, shall we say that a good inventory of the world ought to include “negative” events—failures, omissions, things that didn’t happen—along with positive ones? I argue that we shouldn’t. Talk of non-occurring events is like talk of non-existing objects and should not be taken at face value. We often speak as though there were such things, but deep down we want our words to be interpreted in such a way as to avoid serious (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Refraining.Robert E. Moore - 1979 - Philosophical Studies 36 (4):407 - 424.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A Theory of Human Action.Alvin Ira Goldman - 1970 - Englewood Cliffs, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   483 citations  
  • Reactive attitudes, reactivity, and omissions. [REVIEW]Alfred R. Mele - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (2):447-452.
    Regarding a recent book of mine, John Fischer wrote : “I am faced with the difficult task of doing a critical notice of a book, with almost all of which I agree!” I face a similar task here. Fischer and Ravizza’s Responsibility and Control is an excellent book. It develops, in admirable detail, an attractive compatibilist position on moral responsibility in a trio of related spheres—actions, consequences, and omissions—and it presents powerful objections to leading arguments for incompatibilism. Incompatibilists undoubtedly will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Acts and Other Events.Judith Jarvis Thomson - 1979 - Philosophy 54 (208):253-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Causation By Omission: A Dilemma.Sarah McGrath - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 123 (1-2):125-148.
    Some omissions seem to be causes. For example, suppose Barry promises to water Alice’s plant, doesn’t water it, and that the plant then dries up and dies. Barry’s not watering the plant – his omitting to water the plant – caused its death. But there is reason to believe that if omissions are ever causes, then there is far more causation by omission than we ordinarily think. In other words, there is reason to think the following thesis true.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • (1 other version)Norm and Action: A Logical Enquiry.Georg Henrik von Wright - 1963 - New York, NY, USA: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
    This work has been selected by scholars as being culturally important and is part of the knowledge base of civilization as we know it. This work is in the public domain in the United States of America, and possibly other nations. Within the United States, you may freely copy and distribute this work, as no entity has a copyright on the body of the work. Scholars believe, and we concur, that this work is important enough to be preserved, reproduced, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • Acts and other events.Judith Jarvis Thomson - 1977 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Contemplating failure: The importance of unconscious omission.Patricia G. Smith - 1990 - Philosophical Studies 59 (2):159 - 176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Two concepts of causation.Ned Hall - 2004 - In John Collins, Ned Hall & Laurie Paul (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals. MIT Press. pp. 225-276.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   339 citations  
  • (1 other version)Norm and Action. A Logical Enquiry.Georg Henrik von Wright - 1965 - Philosophy 40 (151):77-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • (1 other version)Intention.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1957 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57:321-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1055 citations  
  • Responsibility and Failure.John Martin Fischer - 1986 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86:251 - 270.
    John Martin Fischer; XIV*—Responsibility and Failure, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 86, Issue 1, 1 June 1986, Pages 251–272, https://doi.org/1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Omissions.Frederick Adrian Siegler - 1968 - Analysis 28 (3):98 - 106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • XIV*—Responsibility and Failure.John Martin Fischer - 1986 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86 (1):251-272.
    John Martin Fischer; XIV*—Responsibility and Failure, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 86, Issue 1, 1 June 1986, Pages 251–272, https://doi.org/1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Intentional omissions.Randolph Clarke - 2010 - Noûs 44 (1):158-177.
    It is argued that intentionally omitting requires having an intention with relevant content. And the intention must play a causal role with respect to one’s subsequent thought and conduct. Even if omissions cannot be caused, an account of intentional omission must be causal. There is a causal role for one’s reasons as well when one intentionally omits to do something.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • (1 other version)Ifs and Cans1.J. L. Austin, G. J. Warnock & J. O. Urmson - 1961 - In John Langshaw Austin (ed.), Philosophical Papers. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    Criticises G. E. Moore’s highly influential proposal that ascriptions of agent ability implying freedom of choice or action, what the agent could do, are analyzable as conditional statements regarding what the agent would do under certain circumstances. Austin objects against Moore that some uses of ‘if’ are non-conditional and goes on to examine the uses of these non-conditional cases. Moore’s proposal also lies at the heart of some compatibilist theories of free will and determinism. Austin argues determinism to be a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Taking some of the mystery out of omissions.Michael J. Zimmerman - 1981 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 19 (4):541-554.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Refraining, Omitting, and Negative Acts.Kent Bach - 2010 - In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 50–57.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Ways of Failing to Do Something Refraining Omitting Negative Acts: Inaction as Action? References.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Reply to Strawson'.D. Davidson - 1985 - In Bruce Vermazen & Merrill B. Hintikka (eds.), Essays on Davidson: actions and events. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Feinberg and the Failure to Act.Patricia Smith - 2005 - Legal Theory 11 (3):237-250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Absences, Possible Causation, and the Problem of Non-Locality.Phil Dowe - 2009 - The Monist 92 (1):23-40.
    I argue that so-called ‘absence causation’must be treated in terms of counterfactuals about causation such as ‘had a occurred, a would have caused b’. First, I argue that some theories of causation that accept absence causation are unattractive because they undermine the idea of possible causation. And second, I argue that accepting absence causation violates a principle commonly associated with relativity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)Agency and mental action.Alfred R. Mele - 1997 - Philosophical Perspectives 11:231-249.
    My question here is whether there are intentional mental actions that generate special, significant threats to causalism (i.e., threats of a kind not generated by intentional overt actions), or that generate, more poi- gnantly, problems for causalism that some intentional overt actions allegedly generate, as well.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Omitting, Refraining and Letting Happen.Douglas N. Walton - 1980 - American Philosophical Quarterly 17 (4):319 - 326.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Ethics and action theory on refraining: A familiar refrain in two parts. [REVIEW]Patricia G. Smith - 1986 - Journal of Value Inquiry 20 (1):3-17.
    We can see from the analysis set out here that the two accounts that were the focus of consideration are complementary to one another. It has been my contention that a problem like specifying a concept such as ‘refrain’ is highly complex. One part of it is the problem of determining the relation between the action (or event) and the result. Another part of the problem is that of describing the event itself; what kind of an event is it? These (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Language of Not Doing.Myles Brand - 1971 - American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1):45 - 53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Freedom and forbearance.Arthur Danto - 1966 - In Keith Lehrer (ed.), Freedom and Determinism. Contributors: Roderick M. Chisholm And Others. New York,: Random House. pp. 45--63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations