Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Imagination and the aesthetic appreciation of nature.Emily Brady - 1998 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56 (2):139-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The postmodern sublime: Kant and Tony Smith's anecdote of the cube.Paul G. Beidler - 1995 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (2):177-186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An essay on the sublime (1747).J. Baillie - 1953 - Los Angeles,: William Andrews Clark Memorial Library, University of California.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Awe or envy: Herder contra Kant on the sublime.Rachel Zuckert - 2003 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 61 (3):217–232.
    I present and evaluate Johann Gottfried Herder's criticisms of Kant's account of the sublime and Herder's own theory of the sublime, as presented in his work, Kalligone. Herder's account and criticisms ought to be taken seriously, I argue, as (respectively) a non-reductive, naturalist aesthetics of the sublime, and as illuminating the metaphysical, moral, and political presuppositions underlying Kant's (and Burke's) accounts of the sublime.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Physiological Sublime: Burke's Critique of Reason.Vanessa Lyndal Ryan - 2001 - Journal of the History of Ideas 62 (2):265-279.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Ideas 62.2 (2001) 265-279 [Access article in PDF] The Physiological Sublime: Burke's Critique of Reason Vanessa L. Ryan The eighteenth-century discussion of the sublime is primarily concerned not with works of art but with how a particular experience of being moved impacts the self. The discussion of the sublime most fully explores the question of how we make sense of our experience: "Why and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • How is a theory of the sublime possible?Guy Sircello - 1993 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (4):541-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Somaesthetics and Burke's sublime.Richard Shusterman - 2005 - British Journal of Aesthetics 45 (4):323-341.
    Burke is an important exception to Nietzsche's claim that philosophical aesthetics ignores physiology and the role of practical interest. Grounded on the powerful interest of survival, Burke's theory of the sublime also offers a physiological explanation of our feelings of sublimity that explicitly defines certain conditions of our nerves as the ‘efficient cause’ of such feelings. While his general account of sublimity is widely appreciated, its somatic dimension has been dismissed as hopelessly misguided. In examining Burke's views in relation to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Expressive perception as projective imagining.Paul Noordhof - 2008 - Mind and Language 23 (3):329–358.
    I argue that our experience of expressive properties (such as the joyfulness or sadness of a piece of music) essentially involves the sensuous imagination (through simulation) of an emotion-guided process which would result in the production of the properties which constitute the realisation of the expressive properties experienced. I compare this proposal with arousal theories, Wollheim’s Freudian account, and other more closely related theories appealing to imagination such as Kendall Walton’s. I explain why the proposal is most naturally developed in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Space, time and the sublime in Hume's treatise.Justine Noel - 1994 - British Journal of Aesthetics 34 (3):218-225.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The shared circuits model (SCM): How control, mirroring, and simulation can enable imitation, deliberation, and mindreading.Susan Hurley - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (1):1-22.
    Imitation, deliberation, and mindreading are characteristically human sociocognitive skills. Research on imitation and its role in social cognition is flourishing across various disciplines. Imitation is surveyed in this target article under headings of behavior, subpersonal mechanisms, and functions of imitation. A model is then advanced within which many of the developments surveyed can be located and explained. The shared circuits model (SCM) explains how imitation, deliberation, and mindreading can be enabled by subpersonal mechanisms of control, mirroring, and simulation. It is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • The shared circuits model. How control, mirroring, and simulation can enable imitation and mind reading.Susan Hurley - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (1):1-22.
    Imitation, deliberation, and mindreading are characteristically human sociocognitive skills. Research on imitation and its role in social cognition is flourishing across various disciplines; it is here surveyed under headings of behavior, subpersonal mechanisms, and functions of imitation. A model is then advanced within which many of the developments surveyed can be located and explained. The shared circuits model explains how imitation, deliberation, and mindreading can be enabled by subpersonal mechanisms of control, mirroring and simulation. It is cast at a middle, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • The brain's concepts: The role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual knowledge.Vittorio Gallese & George Lakoff - 2007 - Cognitive Neuropsychology 22 (3-4):455-479.
    Concepts are the elementary units of reason and linguistic meaning. They are conventional and relatively stable. As such, they must somehow be the result of neural activity in the brain. The questions are: Where? and How? A common philosophical position is that all concepts—even concepts about action and perception—are symbolic and abstract, and therefore must be implemented outside the brain’s sensory-motor system. We will argue against this position using (1) neuroscientific evidence; (2) results from neural computation; and (3) results about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   197 citations  
  • Empathy for Objects1.Gregory Currie - 2011 - In Amy Coplan & Peter Goldie (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. Oxford University Press. pp. 82.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Infectious music: Music-listener emotional contagion.Stephen Davies - 2011 - In Amy Coplan & Peter Goldie (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations