Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Can a Nonconsequentialist Count Lives?Alan Strudler David Wasserman - 2003 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (1):71-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Saving People and Flipping Coins.Ben Bradley - 2008 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 3 (1):1-13.
    Suppose you find yourself in a situation in which you can either save both A and B or save only C. A, B and C are relevantly similar – all are strangers to you, none is more deserving of life than any other, none is responsible for being in a life-threatening situation, and so on. John Taurek argued that when deciding what to do in such a situation, you should flip a coin, thereby giving each of A, B and C (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Numbers Problem.Nien-hê Hsieh, Alan Strudler & David Wasserman - 2006 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (4):352-372.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • A theory of justice.John Rawls - unknown
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4025 citations  
  • Anarchy, State, and Utopia.Robert Nozick - 1974 - New York: Basic Books.
    Winner of the 1975 National Book Award, this brilliant and widely acclaimed book is a powerful philosophical challenge to the most widely held political and social positions of our age--liberal, socialist, and conservative.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1974 citations  
  • A Theory of Justice: Original Edition.John Rawls - 2009 - Belknap Press.
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition. This reissue makes the first edition once again available for scholars and serious students of Rawls's work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3464 citations  
  • What we owe to each other.Thomas Scanlon - 1998 - Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    In this book, T. M. Scanlon offers new answers to these questions, as they apply to the central part of morality that concerns what we owe to each other.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2438 citations  
  • Deontic Cycling and the Structure of Commonsense Morality.Tim Willenken - 2012 - Ethics 122 (3):545-561.
    A range of extremely plausible moral principles turn out to generate “deontic cycling”: sets of actions wherein I have stronger reason to do B than A, C than B, and A than C. Indeed, just about anything recognizable as commonsense morality generates deontic cycling. This matters for two reasons. First, it creates a problem for the widely held view that agent-centered rankings can square consequentialism with commonsense morality. Second, it forces a choice between some deeply plausible views about rationality—wherein someone (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Can a Nonconsequentialist Count Lives?David Wasserman & Alan Strudler - 2003 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (1):71-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The individualist lottery: How people count, but not their numbers.Jens Timmermann - 2004 - Analysis 64 (2):106–112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The individualist lottery: how people count, but not their numbers.J. Timmermann - 2004 - Analysis 64 (2):106-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Numbers, with and without contractualism.Joseph Raz - 2003 - Ratio 16 (4):346–367.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The moral importance of selecting people randomly.Martin Peterson - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (6):321–327.
    This article discusses some ethical principles for distributing pandemic influenza vaccine and other indivisible goods. I argue that a number of principles for distributing pandemic influenza vaccine recently adopted by several national governments are morally unacceptable because they put too much emphasis on utilitarian considerations, such as the ability of the individual to contribute to society. Instead, it would be better to distribute vaccine by setting up a lottery. The argument for this view is based on a purely consequentialist account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Skepticism about Saving the Greater Number.Michael Otsuka - 2004 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 32 (4):413-426.
    Suppose that each of the following four conditions obtains: 1. You can save either a greater or a lesser number of innocent people from (equally) serious harm. 2. You can do so at trivial cost to yourself. 3. If you act to save, then the harm you prevent is harm that would not have been prevented if you had done nothing. 4. All other things are equal. A skeptic about saving the greater number rejects the common-sensical claim that you have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Saving lives, moral theory, and the claims of individuals.Michael Otsuka - 2006 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (2):109–135.
    Philosophy & Public Affairs, 34 (2006): 109-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Scanlon and the claims of the many versus the one.Michael Otsuka - 2000 - Analysis 60 (3):288-293.
    In "What We Owe to Each Other", T. M. Scanlon argues that one should save the greater number when faced with the choice between saving one life and two or more different lives. It is, Scanlon claims, a virtue of this argument that it does not appeal to the claims of groups of individuals but only to the claims of individuals. I demonstrate that this argument for saving the greater number, indeed, depends, contrary to what Scanlon says, upon an appeal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • The Possibility of Altruism. [REVIEW]Bernard Gert - 1972 - Journal of Philosophy 69 (12):340-344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • The possibility of altruism.Thomas Nagel - 1970 - Oxford,: Clarendon P..
    Just as there are rational requirements on thought, there are rational requirements on action. This book defends a conception of ethics, and a related conception of human nature, according to which altruism is included among the basic rational requirements on desire and action. Altruism itself depends on the recognition of the reality of other persons, and on the equivalent capacity to regard oneself as merely one individual among many.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   521 citations  
  • How to be consistent without saving the greater number.Kirsten Meyer - 2006 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (2):136–146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Sports Rules, Their Spirit and the Oldest Knockout Competition of Them All.Mike McNamee - 2009 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 3 (1):1-2.
    (2009). Sports Rules, Their Spirit and the Oldest Knockout Competition of Them All. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy: Vol. 3, No. 1, pp. 1-2. doi: 10.1080/17511320902752300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Who Is Afraid of Numbers?S. Matthew Liao - 2008 - Utilitas 20 (4):447-461.
    In recent years, many non-consequentialists such as Frances Kamm and Thomas Scanlon have been puzzling over what has come to be known as the Number Problem, which is how to show that the greater number in a rescue situation should be saved without aggregating the claims of the many, a typical kind of consequentialist move that seems to violate the separateness of persons. In this article, I argue that these non-consequentialists may be making the task more difficult than necessary, because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Taurek, numbers and probabilities.Rob Lawlor - 2006 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 9 (2):149 - 166.
    In his paper, “Should the Numbers Count?" John Taurek imagines that we are in a position such that we can either save a group of five people, or we can save one individual, David. We cannot save David and the five. This is because they each require a life-saving drug. However, David needs all of the drug if he is to survive, while the other five need only a fifth each.Typically, people have argued as if there was a choice to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Contractualism on saving the many.R. Kumar - 2001 - Analysis 61 (2):165-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Precis of Morality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from ItMorality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from It. [REVIEW]Frances Kamm - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (4):939.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Morality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from It.Frances Kamm - 1998 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 58 (4):963-967.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Aggregation and two moral methods.F. M. Kamm - 2005 - Utilitas 17 (1):1-23.
    I begin by reconsidering the arguments of John Taurek and Elizabeth Anscombe on whether the number of people we can help counts morally. I then consider arguments that numbers should count given by F. M. Kamm and Thomas Scanlon, and criticism of them by Michael Otsuka. I examine how different conceptions of the moral method known as pairwise comparison are at work in these different arguments and what the ideas of balancing and tie-breaking signify for decision-making in various types of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Saving the greater number without combining claims.Iwao Hirose - 2001 - Analysis 61 (4):341–342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Saving the greater number without combining claims.I. Hirose - 2001 - Analysis 61 (4):341-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons.Iwao Hirose - 2013 - Utilitas 25 (2):182-205.
    Many critics of utilitarianism claim that we should reject interpersonal aggregation because aggregative principles do not take the separateness of persons seriously. In this article, I will reject this claim. I will first elucidate the theoretical structure of aggregation. I will then consider various interpretations of the notion of the separateness of persons and clarify what exactly those critics are trying to reject by appealing to the notion of the separateness of persons. I will argue that none of these interpretations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Saving the Few.Tyler Doggett - 2011 - Noûs 47 (2):302-315.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • What Is Wrong With Kamm's and Scanlon's Arguments Against Taurek.Tyler Doggett - 2009 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 3 (3):1-16.
    I distinguish several arguments Kamm and Scanlon make against Taurek's claim that it is permissible to save smaller groups of people rather than larger. I then argue that none succeeds. This is a companion to my "Saving the Few.".
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Anarchy, State, and Utopia.Robert Nozick - 1974 - Philosophy 52 (199):102-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1980 citations  
  • What We Owe to Each Other.Thomas Scanlon - 2002 - Mind 111 (442):323-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1427 citations  
  • Précis of Morality, Mortality, Vol. 1.Frances Kamm - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (4):939-945.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Should the numbers count?John Taurek - 1977 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (4):293-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   247 citations  
  • Innumerate ethics.Derek Parfit - 1978 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 7 (4):285-301.
    Suppose that we can help either one person or many others. Is it a reason t0 help the many that We should thus be helping more people? John Taurek thinks not. We may learn from his arguments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • [Book review] morality, mortality. [REVIEW]Frances Myrna Kamm - 1995 - Hastings Center Report 25 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Why the numbers should sometimes count.John T. Sanders - 1988 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 17 (1):3-14.
    John Taurek has argued that, where choices must be made between alternatives that affect different numbers of people, the numbers are not, by themselves, morally relevant. This is because we "must" take "losses-to" the persons into account (and these don't sum), but "must not" consider "losses-of" persons (because we must not treat persons like objects). I argue that the numbers are always ethically relevant, and that they may sometimes be the decisive consideration.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations