Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. VII.—Sentences About Believing.Roderick M. Chisholm - 1956 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56 (1):125-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Free will and the Asymmetrical Justifiability of Holding Morally Responsible.Benjamin Vilhauer - 2015 - Philosophical Quarterly 65 (261):772-789.
    This paper is about an asymmetry in the justification of praising and blaming behaviour which free will theorists should acknowledge even if they do not follow Wolf and Nelkin in holding that praise and blame have different control conditions. That is, even if praise and blame have the same control condition, we must have stronger reasons for believing that it is satisfied to treat someone as blameworthy than we require to treat someone as praiseworthy. Blaming behaviour which involves serious harm (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Metaphysics.Archie J. Bahm - 1964 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 25 (1):147-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Teleological Realism: Mind, Agency, and Explanation.Carolyn Price - 2007 - Philosophical Quarterly 57 (228):501-503.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Action explanation and the free will debate: How incompatibilist arguments go wrong1.Scott Sehon - 2012 - Philosophical Issues 22 (1):351-368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A flawed conception of determinism in the Consequence Argument.S. Sehon - 2011 - Analysis 71 (1):30-38.
    According to the Consequence Argument, the truth of determinism plus other plausible principles would yield the conclusion that we have no free will. In this paper I will argue that the conception of determinism typically employed in the various versions of the Consequence Argument is not plausible. In particular, I will argue that, taken most straightforwardly, determinism as defined in the Consequence Argument would imply that the existence of God is logically impossible. This is quite an implausible result. The truth (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Issue Introduction.Martin Schönfeld - 2010 - Essays in Philosophy 11 (1):1-7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Determinism, Laws of Nature and the Consequence Argument.Pedro Merlussi - 2016 - Manuscrito 39 (1):73-95.
    Scott Sehon argues that the conception of determinism employed in the Consequence Argument is implausible because it rules out the logical possibility of the laws of nature being violated. Sehon says, for instance, that determinism is incompatible with the logical possibility of an interventionist God. His objection to the Consequence Argument boils down to a way of reading the box in what is implied by van Inwagen's conception of determinism. Sehon reads the box as logical necessity, and this clearly precludes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • ‘Determinism’ Is Just Fine: A Reply to Scott Sehon.Gabriel Marco - 2016 - Philosophia 44 (2):469-477.
    Scott Sehon recently argued that the standard notion of determinism employed in the Consequence Argument makes it so that, if our world turns out to be deterministic, then an interventionist God is logically impossible. He further argues that because of this, we should revise our notion of determinism. In this paper I show that Sehon’s argument for the claim that the truth of determinism, in this sense, would make an interventionist God logically impossible ultimately fails. I then offer and respond (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hard-heartedness and Libertarianism.John Lemos - 2013 - Philo 16 (2):180-195.
    Richard Double argues that libertarians believe we should hold people morally responsible for their actions and we must possess libertarian free will to be morally responsible for our actions; most libertarians believe there is scant epistemic justification for the belief that any of us possess LFW; and morally conscientious persons hold people responsible for their actions only if they have epistemic justification for their guilt. Thus, he concludes most libertarians are not being morally conscientious when they hold people responsible for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Hard-heartedness and Libertarianism Again.John Lemos - 2017 - Journal of Philosophical Research 42:319-323.
    In a recent article, I defended libertarian views of free will against Richard Double’s argument that such views are hard-hearted. In supporting my main argument against Double, I invoked what I call “the Puppetmaster” argument. Double has recently countered that this argument fails. In this essay, I provide a response to this negative assessment of the Puppetmaster argument.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Moral Hardness of Libertarianism.Richard Double - 2002 - Philo 5 (2):226-234.
    The following is a criticism designed to apply to most libertarian free will theorists. I argue that most libertarians hold three beliefs that jointly show them to be unsympathetic or hard-hearted to persons whom they hold morally responsible: that persons are morally responsible only because they make libertarian choices, that we should hold persons responsible, and that we lack epistemic justification for thinking persons make such choices. Softhearted persons who held these three beliefs would espouse hard determinism, which exonerates all (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Hard-Heartedness of some Libertarians.Richard Double - 2017 - Journal of Philosophical Research 42:313-318.
    In “The Moral Hardness of Libertarianism”, I accuse libertarians of being morally unsympathetic if they hold three widely shared beliefs: that persons are morally responsible only if they make libertarian choices; that we should hold persons morally responsible; and that we lack epistemic justification for thinking persons make libertarian choices. In “Hard-Heartedness and Libertarianism”, John Lemos, relying on the Kantian principle of ends, suggests a way for libertarians to accept these three beliefs while avoiding the charge of hard-heartedness. In this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Response to Fischer, Pereboom, and Vargas.Robert Kane - 2007 - In John Martin Fischer (ed.), Four Views on Free Will. Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Response to Kane, Fischer, and Vargas.Derk Pereboom - 2007 - In John Martin Fischer (ed.), Four Views on Free Will. Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Hard incompatibilism.Derk Pereboom - 2007 - In John Martin Fischer (ed.), Four Views on Free Will. Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):278-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2807 citations  
  • Four Views on Free Will.John Martin Fischer, Robert Kane & Derk Pereboom Y. Manuel Vargas - 2007 - Critica 39 (117):96-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Purpose, Cause, and Supervenience.Michael L. Corrado - 2010 - Essays in Philosophy 11 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations