Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Review: Non-Consequentialism, the Person as an End-in-Itself, and the Significance of Status. [REVIEW]Frances Kamm - 1992 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 21 (4):354 - 389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Cummiskey's Kantian Consequentialism.Richard Dean - 2000 - Utilitas 12 (1):25.
    In Kantian Consequentialism, David Cummiskey argues that the central ideas of Kant's moral philosophy provide claims about value which, if applied consistently, lead to consequentialist normative principles. While Kant himself was not a consequentialist, Cummiskey thinks he should have been, given his fundamental positions in ethics. I argue that Cummiskey is mistaken. Cummiskey's argument relies on a non-Kantian idea about value, namely that value can be defined, and objects with value identified, conceptually prior to and independent of the choices that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Alienation, consequentialism, and the demands of morality.Peter Railton - 1984 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (2):134-171.
    The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   411 citations  
  • Agent-centered restrictions: Clearing the air of paradox.Paul Hurley - 1997 - Ethics 108 (1):120-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Contractualism and deontic restrictions.Jeffrey Brand-Ballard - 2004 - Ethics 114 (2):269-300.
    In response to the charge that deontic ("argent-centered") restrictions are paradoxical, several recent writers suggest that such restrictions find support within T.M. Scanlon's contractualism. I suggest that this claim is only interesting if these restrictions are stronger than those supported by indirect consequentialism. I argue that contractualism cannot support restrictions any stronger than those supported by indirect consequentialism. The contractualists have mislocated the source of the paradox, which arises under any theory that defines right action in patient-focused terms. Consequentialism and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Demandingness of Scanlon’s Contractualism.Elizabeth Ashford - 2003 - Ethics 113 (2):273-302.
    One of the reasons why Kantian contractualism has been seen as an appealing alternative to utilitarianism is that it seems to be able to avoid utilitarianism's extreme demandingness, while retaining a fully impartial moral point of view. I argue that in the current state of the world, contractualist obligations to help those in need are not significantly less demanding than utilitarian obligations. I also argue that while a plausible version of utilitarianism would be considerably less demanding if the state of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • What We Owe to Each Other.Thomas Scanlon (ed.) - 1998 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    How do we judge whether an action is morally right or wrong? If an action is wrong, what reason does that give us not to do it? Why should we give such reasons priority over our other concerns and values? In this book, T. M. Scanlon offers new answers to these questions, as they apply to the central part of morality that concerns what we owe to each other. According to his contractualist view, thinking about right and wrong is thinking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   286 citations  
  • (2 other versions)A Theory of Justice.John Rawls - unknown
    Since it appeared in 1971, John Rawls's A Theory of Justice has become a classic. The author has now revised the original edition to clear up a number of difficulties he and others have found in the original book. Rawls aims to express an essential part of the common core of the democratic tradition--justice as fairness--and to provide an alternative to utilitarianism, which had dominated the Anglo-Saxon tradition of political thought since the nineteenth century. Rawls substitutes the ideal of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2056 citations  
  • Moral Status and the Impermissibility of Minimizing Violations.Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen - 1996 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 25 (4):333-351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Consequentialism, egoism, and the moral law.David Cummiskey - 1989 - Philosophical Studies 57 (2):111 - 134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Review of Onora O'Neill: Constructions of reason: explorations of Kant's practical philosophy[REVIEW]Stephen Engstrom - 1992 - Ethics 102 (3):653-655.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Value in Ethics and Economics.Paul Seabright - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (2):303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • Saving Scanlon: Contractualism and agent-relativity.Michael Ridge - 2001 - Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (4):472–481.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The Objectivity of Morals and the Subjectivity of Agents.Sarah Conly - 1985 - American Philosophical Quarterly 22 (4):275 - 286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations