Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Malebranche's Theodicy.Andrew G. Black - 1997 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 35 (1):27-44.
    Malebranche's Theodicy ANDREW G. BLACK LEIBNIZ'S SOLUTION tO the problem of evil, his theodicy, might be regarded as a paradigm of philosophical theology. Its pattern, as with so much of Leibniz's philosophy, is reconciliation of deep metaphysical truth with recalcitrant ap- pearance. Thus, a theodicy is not just any solution to the problem; strictly speaking it is a vindication of divine providence in the face of the challenge posed by apparent imperfections of all kinds in creation.' The preeminence of Leibniz's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Critique of the power of judgment.Immanuel Kant - 2000 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Paul Guyer.
    The Critique of the Power of Judgment (a more accurate rendition of what has hitherto been translated as the Critique of Judgment) is the third of Kant's great critiques following the Critique of Pure Reason and the Critique of Practical Reason. This entirely new translation of Kant's masterpiece follows the principles and high standards of all other volumes in The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. This volume includes: for the first time the indispensable first draft of Kant's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   378 citations  
  • Philosophy of mathematics and mathematical practice in the seventeenth century.Paolo Mancosu (ed.) - 1996 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The seventeenth century saw dramatic advances in mathematical theory and practice. With the recovery of many of the classical Greek mathematical texts, new techniques were introduced, and within 100 years, the rules of analytic geometry, geometry of indivisibles, arithmatic of infinites, and calculus were developed. Although many technical studies have been devoted to these innovations, Mancosu provides the first comprehensive account of the relationship between mathematical advances of the seventeenth century and the philosophy of mathematics of the period. Starting with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • The One Possible Basis for a Demonstration of the Existence of God.Immanuel Kant - 1979 - Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press. Edited by Gordon Treash.
    The search for God is dictated not from without but from a profound sense of one's own moral being and worthiness to be happy. The core of Immanuel Kant's argument remains relevant to the experience of ordinary men and women. He wished to strengthen, not undermine, belief in God and in the spiritual nature of humankind. This 1763 essay is imporrtant in understanding the development of Kant's thought. It exposed the flaw in the Cartesian argument that the existence of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone.Immanuel Kant - 1934 - New York: Harper.
    A Monumental Figure of Western Thought Wrestles with the Question of God Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) is one of the most influential philosophers in the history of Western philosophy. His contributions have had a profound impact on almost every philosophical movement that followed him. Kant's teachings on religion were unorthodox in that they were based on rationality rather than revelation. Though logically proving God's existence might be impossible, it is morally reasonable to "act as if there be a God." His strictly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Medieval Aristotelianism and the Case against Secondary Causation in Nature.Alfred J. Freddoso - 1988 - In Thomas V. Morris (ed.), Divine and human action: essays in the metaphysics of theism. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. pp. 74-118.
    Central to the western theistic understanding of divine providence is the conviction that God is the sovereign Lord of nature. He created the physical universe and continually conserves it in existence. What's more, He is always and everywhere active in it by His power. The operations of nature, be they minute or catastrophic, commonplace or unprecedented, are the work of His hands, and without His constant causal influence none of them would or could occur.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Malebranche's occasionalism: A reply to Clarke.Steven M. Nadler - 1995 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (3):505-508.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The problem of secondary causation in Descartes: A response to Des chene.Helen Hattab - 2000 - Perspectives on Science 8 (2):93-118.
    : In this paper I address the vexed question of secondary causation in René Descartes' physics, and examine several influential interpretations, especially the one recently proposed by Dennis Des Chene. I argue that interpreters who regard Cartesian bodies as real secondary causes, on the grounds that the modes of body include real forces, contradict Descartes' account of modes. On the other hand, those who deny that Descartes affirms secondary causation, on the grounds that forces cannot be modes of extension, commit (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Light of the Soul: Theories of Ideas in Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes.Nicholas Jolley - 1990 - Oxford, GB: Clarendon Press.
    The Light of the Soul examines the debate between Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes on the nature of ideas, which was crucial to the development of early modern thinking about the mind and knowledge. Nicholas Jolley guides the reader through the debate and considers its implications for a broad range of issues, such as innate ideas, self-knowledge, scepticism, the mind-body problem, and the creation of the eternal truths, which are as important to philosophy today as they were in the seventeenth century.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Performing the Categories: Eighteenth-Century Generation Theory and the Biological Roots of Kant's A Priori.Phillip R. Sloan - 2002 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 40 (2):229-253.
    Phillip R. Sloan - Performing the Categories: Eighteenth-Century Generation Theory and the Biological Roots of Kant's A Priori - Journal of the History of Philosophy 40:2 Journal of the History of Philosophy 40.2 229-253 Preforming the Categories: Eighteenth-Century Generation Theory and the Biological Roots of Kant's A Priori Phillip R. Sloan Situating Kant's philosophical project in relation to the natural sciences of his day has been of concern to several scholars from both the history of science and the history of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • (1 other version)The light of the soul: theories of ideas in Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes.Nicholas Jolley - 1990 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The concept of an "idea" played a central role in 17th-century theories of mind and knowledge, but philosophers were divided over the nature of ideas. This book examines an important, but little-known, debate on this question in the work of Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes. Looking closely at the issues involved, as well as the particular context in which the debate took place, Jolley demonstrates that the debate has serious implications for a number of major topics in 17th-century philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Occasionalism and general will in Malebranche.Steven M. Nadler - 1993 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 31 (1):31-47.
    This paper examines a common misreading of the mechanics of Malebranche's doctrine of divine causal agency, occasionalism, and its roots in a related misreading of Malebranche's theories. God, contrary to this misreading, is for Malebranche constantly and actively causally engaged in the world, and does not just establish certain laws of nature. The key is in understanding just what Malebranche means by general volitions'.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Malebranche and British philosophy.Charles James McCracken - 1983 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Explores the philosophy of Nicolas Malebranche, the most important seventeenth century philosopher after Descartes and the influence of his philosophy in eighteenth century Britain.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • (1 other version)Natures, Laws, and Miracles: The Roots of Leibniz's Critique of Occasionalism.Donald Rutherford - 1989 - In Steven Nadler (ed.), Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism, and Preestablished Harmony. Pennsylvania State University Press. pp. 135--58.
    Leibniz raises three main objections to the doctrine of occasionalism: (1) it is inconsistent with the supposition of finite substances; (2) it presupposes the occurrence of "perpetual miracles"; (3) it requires that God "disturb" the ordinary laws of nature. At issue in objection (1) is the proper understanding of divine omnipotence, and of the relationship between the power of God and that of created things. I argue that objections (2) and (3), on the other hand, derive from a particular conception (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Malebranche's distinction between general and particular volitions.Andrew Pessin - 2001 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (1):77-99.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.1 (2001) 77-99 [Access article in PDF] Malebranche's Distinction Between General and Particular Volitions Andrew Pessin "God needs no instruments to act," Malebranche writes in Search; "it suffices that He wills in order that a thing be, because it is a contradiction that He should will and that what He wills should not happen. Therefore, His power is His will." 1 God acts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Following Form and Function: A Philosophical Archaeology of Life Science.Stephen T. Asma - 1996 - Northwestern University Press.
    The concepts of form and function have traditionally been defined in terms of biology and then extended to other disciplines. Stephen T. Asma examines the various interpretations of form and function in science and philosophy, reflecting on the philosophical presuppositions underlying the work of Geoffroy, Cuvier, Darwin, and others. -/- In the continental tradition of Canguilhem and Foucault, Asma's treatment of the historical form/function dispute analyzes the complex interactions among ideologies, metaphysical commitments, and research programs. Following Form and Function is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Malebranche and British Philosophy.Charles J. Mccracken - 1985 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 47 (1):128-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Animal Generation and the Mechanical Philosophy: Some Light on the Role of Biology in the Scientific Revolution.Andrew J. Pyle - 1987 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 9 (2):225 - 254.
    In a recent paper, Keith Hutchison has advanced the thesis that the Mechanical Philosophy represents a shift towards supernaturalism in our conception of the physical world. This paper concentrates on one of the great problems of seventeenth-century biological theory — animal generation — to illustrate (and modify) Hutchison's thesis, thereby also serving to locate one role of the life sciences in the Scientific Revolution. This choice of focus enables us to draw heavily on Jacques Roger's seminal work on animal generation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Supernaturalism and the Mechanical Philosophy.Keith Hutchison - 1983 - History of Science 21 (3):297-333.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • What Happened to Occult Qualities in the Scientific Revolution?Keith Hutchison - 1982 - Isis 73 (2):233-253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Preformation and pre-existence in the seventeenth century: A brief analysis.Peter J. Bowler - 1971 - Journal of the History of Biology 4 (2):221-244.
    It is beyond the scope of this paper to describe in detail the rise to popularity of the emboîtement theories during the last decades of the seventeenth century.51 Eventually the theories did gain great influence, but some points emerging from the above discussion indicate that the rise to popularity was not, perhaps, quite as rapid as has sometimes been assumed.52 Although the earlier preformation theories were sometimes regarded as the ancestors of the later ideas,53 there was little intellectual continuity between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The Spontaneous Generation Controversy from Descartes to Oparin.John Farley - 1979 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (1):93-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Occasionalism and the mind-body problem.Steven Nadler - 1997 - In Michael Alexander Stewart (ed.), Studies in seventeenth-century European philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Harvey: Spontaneous generation and the egg.Edward T. Foote - 1969 - Annals of Science 25 (2):139-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Occasionalism and the Cartesian Metaphysic of Motion.T. M. Lennon - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (sup1):29-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Occasionalism and efficacious laws in Malebranche.Nicholas Jolley - 2002 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 26 (1):245–257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • 5 Malebranche on Causation.Steven Nadler - 2000 - In The Cambridge companion to Malebranche. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Machina Ex Deo: William Harvey and the Meaning of Instrument.Don Bates - 2000 - Journal of the History of Ideas 61 (4):577.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A New Artistotle Reader. Aristotle - 1987 - Oxford University Press. Edited by J. L. Ackrill.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations