Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Known Versus Unknown Threats to Internal Validity: A Response to Edwards.Stephen Rice & David Trafimow - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (4):20-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Strategies to Minimize Risks and Exploitation in Phase One Trials on Healthy Subjects.Adil E. Shamoo & David B. Resnik - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (3):W1-W13.
    Most of the literature on phase one trials has focused on ethical and safety issues in research on patients with advanced cancer, but this article focuses on healthy, adult subjects. The article makes six specific recommendations for protecting the rights and welfare of healthy subjects in phase one trials: 1) because phase one trials are short in duaration (usually 1 to 3 months), researchers should gather more data on the short-term and long-term risks of participation in phase one studies by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Note.[author unknown] - 1955 - Annals of Science 11 (4):356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Contractual Duties in Research, Surrogacy, and Stem Cell Donation.John A. Robertson - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (4):13-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Participants' responsibilities in clinical research.David B. Resnik & Elizabeth Ness - 2012 - Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (12):746-750.
    Discussions on the ethics and regulation of clinical research have a great deal to say about the responsibilities of investigators, sponsors, research institutions and institutional review boards, but very little about the responsibilities of research participants. In this article, we discuss the responsibilities of participants in clinical research. We argue that competent adult participants are responsible for complying with study requirements and fulfilling other obligations they undertake when they make an informed choice to enrol in a study. These responsibilities are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Treating Research Subjects as Unskilled Wage Earners: A Risky Business.Nancy King Reame - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2):53-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Facing up to paternalism in research ethics.Franklin G. Miller & Alan Wertheimer - 2007 - Hastings Center Report 37 (3):24-34.
    : Bioethicists have failed to understand the pervasively paternalistic character of research ethics. Not only is the overall structure of research review and regulation paternalistic in some sense; even the way informed consent is sought may imply paternalism. Paternalism has limits, however. Getting clear on the paternalism of research ethics may mean some kinds of prohibited research should be reassessed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • “Through a Glass Darkly”: Researcher Ethnocentrism and the Demonization of Research Participants.John A. Lynch - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (4):22-23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What is wrong with compliance?S. Holm - 1993 - Journal of Medical Ethics 19 (2):108-110.
    Non-compliance is a label often used about patients who do not follow therapeutic advice. This paper analyses the notion of compliance, and tries to show that this notion is inextricably bound to a paternalistic conception of the doctor-patient relationship. It is proposed that we should perhaps not talk so much about the non-compliant patient, but instead shift the focus towards the non-compliant doctor.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Reason, emotion, and love.Mark Fisher - 1977 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 20 (1-4):189 – 203.
    Wittgenstein's private language argument is interpreted as an example of a kind of transcendental argument which, if valid, explains why a certain concept must possess certain features. Cognition and affect are shown to require each other by an application of Bennett's account of what beings capable of true cognition must be capable of, and the necessity of certain emotions to the existence of any rules in a community is argued in similar fashion. Hume's account of love and admiration being rejected, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Strategies to Minimize Risks and Exploitation in Phase One Trials on Healthy Subjects.Adil E. Shamoo - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (3):1-13.
    Most of the literature on phase one trials has focused on ethical and safety issues in research on patients with advanced cancer, but this article focuses on healthy, adult subjects. The article makes six specific recommendations for protecting the rights and welfare of healthy subjects in phase one trials: 1) because phase one trials are short in duaration (usually 1 to 3 months), researchers should gather more data on the short-term and long-term risks of participation in phase one studies by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Assessing the Remedy: The Case for Contracts in Clinical Trials.Sarah J. L. Edwards - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (4):3-12.
    Current orthodoxy in research ethics assumes that subjects of clinical trials reserve rights to withdraw at any time and without giving any reason. This view sees the right to withdraw as a simple extension of the right to refuse to participate all together. In this paper, however, I suggest that subjects should assume some responsibilities for the internal validity of the trial at consent and that these responsibilities should be captured by contract. This would allow the researcher to impose a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Taking a Hard Look at Advocacy in Research. [REVIEW]Rebecca Dresser - 2012 - Hastings Center Report 31 (6):47-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The Case Against Contract: Participant and Investigator Duty in Clinical Trials.Kenneth De Ville - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (4):16-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Noncompliance in AIDS Research.John D. Arras - 1990 - Hastings Center Report 20 (5):24-32.
    Participants in AIDS research may justify noncompliance with protocols by a “coercion defense.” While this defense may not be philosophically successful, a prudent social policy can enhance compliance by encouraging community participation and providing greater access to non‐validated therapies.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Research with biological samples.David Wendler - 2008 - In Ezekiel J. Emanuel (ed.), The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 290--297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Philosophical justifications of informed consent in research.D. Brock, E. J. Emanuel, C. Grady, R. Lie, F. Miller & D. Wendler - 2008 - In Ezekiel J. Emanuel (ed.), The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Deception in the Single-Blind Run-In Phase of Clinical Trials.Howard Mann - 2007 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 29 (2).
    A single-blind run-in phase is often employed in randomized controlled trials. During these types of trials, all participants are given a placebo but are not informed of this fact. In many trials, participants who are judged to be “placebo responders” or who don’t follow instructions for taking the drug are excluded from further participation at the conclusion of this phase. Because participants are not informed of these procedures, this represents the use of deception in research.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Obligation to Participate in Biomedical Research.G. Owen Schaefer, Ezekiel J. Emanuel & Alan Wertheimer - 2009 - Journal of the American Medical Association 302 (1):67-72.
    The current prevailing view is that participation in biomedical research is above and beyond the call of duty. While some commentators have offered reasons against this, we propose a novel public goods argument for an obligation to participate in biomedical research. Biomedical knowledge is a public good, available to any individual even if that individual does not contribute to it. Participation in research is a critical way to support an important public good. Consequently, all have a duty to participate. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations