Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A Theory of Justice: Original Edition.John Rawls - 2009 - Belknap Press.
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition. This reissue makes the first edition once again available for scholars and serious students of Rawls's work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3469 citations  
  • A theory of justice.John Rawls - unknown
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4027 citations  
  • Justification, legitimacy, and social embeddedness: Locke and Rawls on society and the state.Simon Cushing - 2003 - Journal of Value Inquiry 37 (2):217-231.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Idea of a Legitimate State.David Copp - 1999 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 28 (1):3-45.
    A legitimate state would have a right to rule. The problem is to understand, first, precisely what this right amounts to, and second, under what conditions a state would have it. According to the traditional account, the legitimacy of a state is to be explained in terms of its subjects’ obligation to obey the law. I argue that this account is inadequate. I propose that the legitimacy of a state would consist in its having a bundle of rights of various (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Social unity and the identity of persons.David Copp - 2002 - Journal of Political Philosophy 10 (4):365–391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On the Relationship Between Law and Morality.Jules Coleman - 1989 - Ratio Juris 2 (1):66-78.
    Instead of being embarrassed and uneasy about the implications of the separation thesis, positivists should welcome the fact that they cannot account for the obligatoriness of law. The rule of recognition is only a social rule and introduces no grounds for obligation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Presumptive benefits and political obligation.Alan Carter - 2001 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 18 (3):229–243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The normative functions of coercion claims.Mitchell N. Berman - 2002 - Legal Theory 8 (1):45-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Review of Harry Beran: The Consent Theory of Political Obligation[REVIEW]Harry Beran - 1989 - Ethics 99 (4):949-950.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • On Some Criticisms of Consent Theory.Bernard R. Boxill - 1993 - Journal of Social Philosophy 24 (1):81-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The principle of fairness and free-rider problems.Richard J. Arneson - 1982 - Ethics 92 (4):616-633.
    This article references the following linked citations. If you are trying to access articles from an off-campus location, you may be required to first logon via your library web site to access JSTOR. Please visit your library's website or contact a librarian to learn about options for remote access to JSTOR.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Pursuing the good-indirectly.Larry Alexander - 1985 - Ethics 95 (2):315-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Is Law Coercive?William A. Edmundson - 1995 - Legal Theory 1 (1):81-111.
    That law is coercive is something we all more or less take for granted. It is an assumption so rooted in our ways of thinking that it is taken as a given of social reality, an uncontroversial datum. Because it is so regarded, it is infrequently stated, and when it is, it is stated without any hint of possible complications or qualifications. I will call this the “prereflective view,” and I want to examine it with the care it deserves.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Is Law Coercive?William A. Edmundson - 1995 - Legal Theory 1 (1):81-111.
    That lawiscoercive is something we all more or less take for granted. It is an assumption so rooted in our ways of thinking that it is taken as a given of social reality, an uncontroversial datum. Because it is so regarded, it is infrequently stated, and when it is, it is stated without any hint of possible complications or qualifications. I will call this the “prereflective view,” and I want to examine it with the care it deserves.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • What Is the Problem of Political Obligation?Jonathan Wolff - 1991 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91:153 - 169.
    Jonathan Wolff; IX*—What is the Problem of Political Obligation?, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 153–170, https.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Political obligation, fairness, and independence.Jonathan Wolff - 1995 - Ratio 8 (1):87-99.
    In the first section the problem of political obligation is motivated, and in Section 2 the core structure of the problem is laid bare. A recognition ofthis structure prompts reflection that the problem will appear very different to different thinkers, depending on their moral theories. It also invites the speculation that the problem will be incapable of solution on some moral theories while trivial on others. This polarity does reflect the state of much of the literature until fairly recently. However (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • In Defense of Anarchism by Robert Paul Wolff. [REVIEW]Gerald Dworkin - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (18):561-567.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • IX*—What is the Problem of Political Obligation?Jonathan Wolff - 1991 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91 (1):153-170.
    Jonathan Wolff; IX*—What is the Problem of Political Obligation?, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 153–170, https.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Book Review:Ronald Dworkin. Stephen Guest. [REVIEW]William A. Edmundson - 1994 - Ethics 104 (2):394-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Toward a liberal theory of political obligation.Christopher Heath Wellman - 2001 - Ethics 111 (4):735-759.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Relational facts in liberal political theory: Is there magic in the pronoun 'my'?Christopher Heath Wellman - 2000 - Ethics 110 (3):537-562.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Liberalism, Samaritanism, and Political Legitimacy.Christopher Heath Wellman - 1996 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 25 (3):211-237.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Friends, Compatriots, and Special Political Obligations.Christopher Heath Wellman - 2001 - Political Theory 29 (2):217-236.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Associative Allegiances and Political Obligations.Christopher Heath Wellman - 1997 - Social Theory and Practice 23 (2):181-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The moral obligation to obey law.Mark Tunick - 2002 - Journal of Social Philosophy 33 (3):464–482.
    Is it always morally wrong to violate a law and in doing so does one necessarily act badly? I argue that whether in breaking a law one acts badly depends on considerations unique to the particular act of lawbreaking. The moral judgment in question is deeply contextual and cannot be settled by appeal to blanket moral rules such as that it is wrong to break (any) law. The argument is made by focusing on the example of a runner having to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hypothetical Consent and Justification.Cynthia A. Stark - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (6):313.
    Hypothetical contracts have been said to be not worth the paper they are not written on. This paper defends hypothetical consent theories of justice, such as Rawls's, against the view that they lack justificatory power. I argue that while hypothetical consent cannot generate political obligation, it can generate political legitimacy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Review of A. John Simmons: On the Edge of Anarchy: Locke, Consent, and the Limits of Society[REVIEW]Christopher W. Morris - 1995 - Ethics 106 (1):197-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Review of A. John Simmons: Moral Principles and Political Obligations[REVIEW]Charles R. Beitz - 1981 - Ethics 91 (2):309-312.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Justification and legitimacy.A. John Simmons - 1999 - Ethics 109 (4):739-771.
    In this essay I will discuss the relationship between two of the most basic ideas in political and legal philosophy: the justification of the state and state legitimacy. I plainly cannot aspire here to a complete account of these matters; but I hope to be able to say enough to motivate a way of thinking about the relation between these notions that is, I believe, superior to the approach which seems to be dominant in contemporary political philosophy. Today showing that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • Associative political obligations.A. John Simmons - 1996 - Ethics 106 (2):247-273.
    It is claimed by philosophers as diverse as Burke, Walzer, Dworkin, and MacIntyre that our political obligations are best understood as "associative" or "communal" obligations--that is, as obligations that require neither voluntary undertaking nor justification by "external" moral principles, but rather as "local" moral responsibilities whose normative weight derives entirely from their assignment by social practice. This paper identifies three primary lines of argument that appear to support such assertions: conceptual arguments, the arguments of nonvoluntarist contract theory, and communitarian arguments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Relationships and Responsibilities.Samuel Scheffler - 1997 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (3):189-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • Justifying the state.David Schmidtz - 1990 - Ethics 101 (1):89-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Right and the Good.Some Problems in Ethics.W. D. Ross & H. W. B. Joseph - 1933 - Journal of Philosophy 30 (19):517-527.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   355 citations  
  • Two concepts of rules.John Rawls - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (1):3-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   557 citations  
  • Political Liberalism.Stephen Mulhall - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (177):542-545.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  • Political Obligation and the Particularity Requirement.Christopher Heath Wellman - 2004 - Legal Theory 10 (2):97-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Conscience Principle.Mark C. Murphy - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Research 22:387-407.
    My aim is to defend the conscience principle: One ought never to act against the dictates of one’s conscience. In the first part of this paper, I explain what I mean by “conscience” and “dictate of conscience,” and I show that the notion that the conscience principle is inherently anti-authoritarian or inherently fanatical is mistaken. In the second part, I argue that the existence of mistaken conscience does not reduce the conscience principle to absurdity. In the third part, I present (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Conscience Principle.Mark C. Murphy - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Research 22:387-407.
    My aim is to defend the conscience principle: One ought never to act against the dictates of one’s conscience. In the first part of this paper, I explain what I mean by “conscience” and “dictate of conscience,” and I show that the notion that the conscience principle is inherently anti-authoritarian or inherently fanatical is mistaken. In the second part, I argue that the existence of mistaken conscience does not reduce the conscience principle to absurdity. In the third part, I present (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Surrender of judgment and the consent theory of political authority.Mark C. Murphy - 1997 - Law and Philosophy 16 (2):115 - 143.
    The aim of this paper is to take the first steps toward providing a refurbished consent theory of political authority, one that rests in part on a reconception of the relationship between the surrender of judgment and the authoritativeness of political institutions. On the standard view, whatever grounds political authority implies that one ought to surrender one's judgment to that of one's political institutions. On the refurbished view, it is the surrender of one's judgment – which can plausibly be considered (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Natural law, consent, and political obligation.Mark C. Murphy - 2001 - Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (1):70-92.
    There is a story about the connection between the rise of consent theories of political obligation and the fall of natural law theories of political obligation that is popular among political philosophers but nevertheless false. The story is, to put it crudely, that the rise of consent theory in the modern period coincided with, and came as a result of, the fall of the natural law theory that dominated during the medieval period. Neat though it is, the story errs doubly, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Acceptance of Authority and the Duty to Comply with Just Institutions: A Comment on Waldron.Mark C. Murphy - 1994 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 23 (3):271-276.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Review of David Miller: On Nationality[REVIEW]Charles R. Beitz - 1997 - Ethics 108 (1):225-229.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • Special obligations to compatriots.Andrew Mason - 1997 - Ethics 107 (3):427-447.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Law and Content-Independent Reasons.P. Markwick - 2000 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 20 (4):579-596.
    Say a reason to ø is legal just in case at least a part of the reason is the fact that ø-ing is legally required. This paper is about the widely accepted claim that legal reasons have a certain distinctive formal property—content-independence. I argue that, on two important interpretations, this claim is false. It is false either because legal reasons contingently lack the relevant property or because no reason lacks it. I also argue that, given these two interpretations, content-independence could (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Legitimate political authority and the duty of those subject to it: A critique of Edmundson.David Lefkowitz - 2004 - Law and Philosophy 23 (4):399-435.
    According to William Edmundson, a legitimatepolitical authority is one that claims tocreate in its subjects a general duty ofobedience to the law, and that succeeds increating in its subjects a duty to obey stateofficials when they apply the law in particularcases. His argument that legitimate politicalauthority does not require the state''s claim tobe true rests on his analysis of legitimatetheoretical authority, and the assumption thattheoretical and practical authority are thesame in the relevant respects, both of whichare challenged here. In addition, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Coercion and the nature of law.Grant Lamond - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (1):35-57.
    It is a commonplace that coercion forms part of the nature of law: Law is inherently coercive. But how well founded is this claim, and what would it mean for coercion to be part of the of law? This article suggests that the claim is grounded in our current conception of law. The main focus of the article, however, is upon two major lines of argument that attempt to establish a link between law and coercion: one based upon the laws (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The principle of fairness and political obligation.George Klosko - 1987 - Ethics 97 (2):353-362.
    In this now-classic work, he clearly and systematically formulates what others thought impossible_a principle of fairness that specifies a set of conditions which grounds existing political obligations and bridges the gap between the abstract accounts of political principles and the actual beliefs of political actors. Brought up-to-date with a new introduction, this new edition will be of great interest to all interested in political thought.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation.George Klosko - 1991 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    In this now-classic work, he clearly and systematically formulates what others thought impossible_a principle of fairness that specifies a set of conditions which grounds existing political obligations and bridges the gap between the abstract accounts of political principles and the actual beliefs of political actors. Brought up-to-date with a new introduction, this new edition will be of great interest to all interested in political thought.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation.George Klosko (ed.) - 1991 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    In this now-classic work, he clearly and systematically formulates what others thought impossible_a principle of fairness that specifies a set of conditions which grounds existing political obligations and bridges the gap between the abstract accounts of political principles and the actual beliefs of political actors. Brought up-to-date with a new introduction, this new edition will be of great interest to all interested in political thought.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation.George Klosko - 1991 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    In this now-classic work, he clearly and systematically formulates what others thought impossible_a principle of fairness that specifies a set of conditions which grounds existing political obligations and bridges the gap between the abstract accounts of political principles and the actual beliefs of political actors. Brought up-to-date with a new introduction, this new edition will be of great interest to all interested in political thought.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations