Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Relevance Logic.Michael Dunn & Greg Restall - 1983 - In Dov M. Gabbay & Franz Guenthner (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic. Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • (1 other version)Using non-sentences: An application of Relevance Theory.Robert J. Stainton - 1994 - Pragmatics and Cognition 2 (2):269-284.
    Michael Dummett has nicely expressed a rather widespread doctrine about the primacy of sentences. He writes: "you cannot DO anything with a word — cannot effect any conventional act by uttering it — save by uttering some sentence containing that word ...". In this paper we argue that this doctrine is mistaken: it is not only sentences, but also ordinary words and phrases which can be used in isolation. The argument involves two steps. First: we show — using Sperber and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Utterance meaning and syntactic ellipsis.Robert J. Stainton - 1997 - Pragmatics and Cognition 5 (1):51-78.
    Speakers often use ordinary words and phrases, unembedded in any sentence, to perform speech acts—or so it appears. In some cases appearances are deceptive: The seemingly lexical/phrasal utterance may really be an utterance of a syntactically eplliptical sentence. I argue however that, at least sometimes, plain old words and phrases are used on their own. The use of both words/phrases and elliptical sentences leads to two consequences: 1. Context must contribute more to utterance meaning than is often supposed. Here's why: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • What are logical notions?Alfred Tarski - 1986 - History and Philosophy of Logic 7 (2):143-154.
    In this manuscript, published here for the first time, Tarski explores the concept of logical notion. He draws on Klein's Erlanger Programm to locate the logical notions of ordinary geometry as those invariant under all transformations of space. Generalizing, he explicates the concept of logical notion of an arbitrary discipline.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   224 citations  
  • (1 other version)On what grounds what.Jonathan Schaffer - 2009 - In Ryan Wasserman, David Manley & David Chalmers (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 347-383.
    On the now dominant Quinean view, metaphysics is about what there is. Metaphysics so conceived is concerned with such questions as whether properties exist, whether meanings exist, and whether numbers exist. I will argue for the revival of a more traditional Aristotelian view, on which metaphysics is about what grounds what. Metaphysics so revived does not bother asking whether properties, meanings, and numbers exist (of course they do!) The question is whether or not they are fundamental.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   766 citations  
  • (1 other version)Context and logical form.Jason Stanley - 2000 - Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (4):391--434.
    In this paper, I defend the thesis that alleffects of extra-linguistic context on thetruth-conditions of an assertion are traceable toelements in the actual syntactic structure of thesentence uttered. In the first section, I develop thethesis in detail, and discuss its implications for therelation between semantics and pragmatics. The nexttwo sections are devoted to apparent counterexamples.In the second section, I argue that there are noconvincing examples of true non-sentential assertions.In the third section, I argue that there are noconvincing examples of what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   351 citations  
  • Formal and material consequence.Stephen Read - 1994 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 23 (3):247 - 265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • What is logic?Ian Hacking - 1979 - Journal of Philosophy 76 (6):285-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Identity and predication.Gareth Evans - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (13):343-363.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • The cognitive functions of language.Peter Carruthers - 2002 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (6):657-674.
    This paper explores a variety of different versions of the thesis that natural language is involved in human thinking. It distinguishes amongst strong and weak forms of this thesis, dismissing some as implausibly strong and others as uninterestingly weak. Strong forms dismissed include the view that language is conceptually necessary for thought (endorsed by many philosophers) and the view that language is _de facto_ the medium of all human conceptual thinking (endorsed by many philosophers and social scientists). Weak forms include (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   150 citations  
  • Language of thought: The connectionist contribution.Murat Aydede - 1997 - Minds and Machines 7 (1):57-101.
    Fodor and Pylyshyn's critique of connectionism has posed a challenge to connectionists: Adequately explain such nomological regularities as systematicity and productivity without postulating a "language of thought" (LOT). Some connectionists like Smolensky took the challenge very seriously, and attempted to meet it by developing models that were supposed to be non-classical. At the core of these attempts lies the claim that connectionist models can provide a representational system with a combinatorial syntax and processes sensitive to syntactic structure. They are not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • (7 other versions)Conceptual role semantics.Gilbert Harman - 1982 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (April):242-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  • (1 other version)Three Grades of Modal Involvement.W. V. Quine - 1976 - In Willard Van Orman Quine (ed.), The ways of paradox, and other essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. pp. 158-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • (1 other version)Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism.Robert Brandom - 2000 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Robert B. Brandom is one of the most original philosophers of our day, whose book Making It Explicit covered and extended a vast range of topics in metaphysics, epistemology, and philosophy of language--the very core of analytic philosophy. This new work provides an approachable introduction to the complex system that Making It Explicit mapped out. A tour of the earlier book's large ideas and relevant details, Articulating Reasons offers an easy entry into two of the main themes of Brandom's work: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Ontological Nihilism.Jason Turner - 2011 - Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 6:3-54.
    Ontological nihilism is the radical-sounding thesis that there is nothing at all. This chapter first discusses how the most plausible forms of this thesis aim to be slightly less radical than they sound and what they will have to do in order to succeed in their less radical ambitions. In particular, they will have to paraphrase sentences of best science into ontologically innocent counterparts. The chapter then points out the defects in two less plausible strategies, before going on to argue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology.Ned Block - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):615-678.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   347 citations  
  • The Varieties of Reference.Gareth Evans & John Mcdowell - 1986 - Philosophy 61 (238):534-538.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   692 citations  
  • The Language of Thought.J. A. Fodor - 1978 - Critica 10 (28):140-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1455 citations  
  • Individuals.P. F. Strawson - 1959 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 14 (2):246-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   900 citations  
  • (1 other version)Pursuit of Truth.W. V. O. Quine - 1990 - Philosophy 65 (253):384-385.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   251 citations  
  • The Bounds of Logic: A Generalized Viewpoint.Gila Sher - 1991 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (4):1078-1083.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • A Subject with No Object: Strategies for Nominalistic Interpretation of Mathematics.John Burgess & Gideon Rosen - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 50 (198):124-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Being Explained Away.John P. Burgess - 2005 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 13 (2):41-56.
    When I first began to take an interest in the debate over nominalism in philosophy of mathematics, some twenty-odd years ago, the issue had already been under discussion for about a half-century. The terms of the debate had been set: W. V. Quine and others had given “abstract,” “nominalism,” “ontology,” and “Platonism” their modern meanings. Nelson Goodman had launched the project of the nominalistic reconstruction of science, or of the mathematics used in science, in which Quine for a time had (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Non-sentential assertions and semantic ellipsis.Robert J. Stainton - 1995 - Linguistics and Philosophy 18 (3):281 - 296.
    The restricted semantic ellipsis hypothesis, we have argued, is committed to an enormous number of multiply ambiguous expressions, the introduction of which gains us no extra explanatory power. We should, therefore, reject it. We should also spurn the original version since: (a) it entails the restricted version and (b) it incorrectly declares that, whenever a speaker makes an assertion by uttering an unembedded word or phrase, the expression uttered has illocutionary force.Once rejected, the semantic ellipsis hypothesis cannot account for the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • What is a logical constant?Christopher Peacocke - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (9):221-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • (7 other versions)(Nonsolipsistic) conceptual role semantics.Gilbert Harman - 1987 - In Ernest LePore (ed.), New directions in semantics. Orlando: Academic Press. pp. 55–81.
    CRS says that the meanings of expressions of a language or other symbol system or the contents of mental states are determined and explained by the way symbols are used in thinking. According to CRS one.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • What is Logical Form?Ernie Lepore & Kirk Ludwig - 2002 - In Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter (eds.), Logical Form and Language. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    This paper articulates and defends a conception of logical form as semantic form revealed by a compositional meaning theory. On this conception, the logical form of a sentence is determined by the semantic types of its primitive terms and their mode of combination as it relates to determining under what conditions it is true. We develop this idea in the framework of truth-theoretic semantics. We argue that the semantic form of a declarative sentence in a language L is revealed by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The language of thought and natural language understanding.Jonathan Knowles - 1998 - Analysis 58 (4):264-272.
    Stephen Laurence and Eric Margolis have recently argued that certain kinds of regress arguments against the language of thought (LOT) hypothesis as an account of how we understand natural languages have been answered incorrectly or inadequately by supporters of LOT ('Regress arguments against the language of thought', Analysis, 57 (1), 60-6, J 97). They argue further that this does not undermine the LOT hypothesis, since the main sources of support for LOT are (or might be) independent of it providing an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (2 other versions)On the Very idea of a Conceptual Scheme.Donald Davidson - 1984 - In Inquiries Into Truth And Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. pp. 183-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   238 citations  
  • Predicate functors revisited.W. V. Quine - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (3):649-652.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • On Mental Entities.Willard V. Quine - 1976 - In Willard Van Orman Quine (ed.), The ways of paradox, and other essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Towards ontological nihilism.John O'Leary-Hawthorne & Andrew Cortens - 1995 - Philosophical Studies 79 (2):143 - 165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • The doctrine of logic as form.John Etchemendy - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (3):319 - 334.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • (7 other versions)Conceptual role semantics.Mark Greenberg & Gilbert Harman - 1982 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23 (2):242-256.
    CRS says that the meanings of expressions of a language or other symbol system or the contents of mental states are determined and explained by the way symbols are used in thinking. According to CRS one.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • (1 other version)Using non-sentences: An application of Relevance Theory.Robert J. Stainton - 1994 - Pragmatics and Cognition 2 (2):269-284.
    Michael Dummett has nicely expressed a rather widespread doctrine about the primacy of sentences. He writes: "you cannot DO anything with a word — cannot effect any conventional act by uttering it — save by uttering some sentence containing that word...". In this paper we argue that this doctrine is mistaken: it is not only sentences, but also ordinary words and phrases which can be used in isolation. The argument involves two steps. First: we show — using Sperber and Wilson's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (1 other version)Précis of A Study of Concepts. [REVIEW]Christopher Peacocke - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2):407.
    The principal thesis of A Study of Concepts is that a concept is individuated by its possession condition. Concepts are here understood to be sliced as finely as epistemic possibility. So now and 6 o’clock are different concepts, even if, in context, they pick out the same time; likewise for the observational concept circular and the complex concept locus of coplanar points equidistant from a given point. In the simplest cases, a possession condition is stated by giving a true, individuating (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (7 other versions)Conceptual role semantics.Gilbert Harman - 1982 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23:242-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • Logical Forms: An Introduction to Philosophical Logic.T. S. Champlin & Mark Sainsbury - 1992 - Philosophical Quarterly 42 (167):243.
    Logical Forms explains both the detailed problems involved in finding logical forms and also the theoretical underpinnings of philosophical logic. In this revised edition, exercises are integrated throughout the book. The result is a genuinely interactive introduction which engages the reader in developing the argument. Each chapter concludes with updated notes to guide further reading.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Logical form in natural language: A precis.William G. Lycan - 1989 - Philosophical Psychology 2 (1):31 – 35.
    This book's purpose is to detail the anatomy of linguistic meaning, showing how the various elements of meaning fit together. part 1 defends the truth-theoretic conception of semantics, taking the notion of a sentence's truth-condition as the core of meaning. part 2 explores the complex interconnections between syntax, semantics and various pragmatic notions and attempts to reconcile the apparent differences between natural and formal language. part 3 examines the relation between semantics and psychology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The idea of a logical constant.Timothy McCarthy - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (9):499-523.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • An axiomatization of predicate functor logic.Steven T. Kuhn - 1983 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 24 (2):233-241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Concept of Logical Consequence.John Etchemendy - 1990 - Mind 100 (3):382-385.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   170 citations