Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)After Virtue.A. MacIntyre - 1981 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 46 (1):169-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1727 citations  
  • Democracy and Disagreement.Amy Gutmann & Dennis Thompson - 1996 - Ethics 108 (3):607-610.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   442 citations  
  • A Theory of Justice: Original Edition.John Rawls - 2005 - Belknap Press.
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition. This reissue makes the first edition once again available for scholars and serious students of Rawls's work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3563 citations  
  • Children: Rights and Childhood (3rd edition).David Archard - 2014 - Routledge.
    Children: Rights and Childhood is widely regarded as the first book to offer a detailed philosophical examination of children’s rights. David Archard provides a clear and accessible introduction to a topic that has assumed increasing relevance since the book’s first publication. -/- The third edition has been fully revised and updated throughout with a new chapter providing an in-depth analysis of the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child (UNCRC) and Part 2 has been restructured to move the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • Deliberative Democracy: A Sympathetic Comment.Samuel Freeman - 2000 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 29 (4):371-418.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Becoming versus being: A critical analysis of the child in liberal theory.Barbara Arneil - 2004 - In David Archard (ed.), The moral and political status of children. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 70--96.
    The excessive faith liberal theorists have had in the power of rights and rights discourse can have deleterious consequences for children. As vulnerable and dependent beings, children need to be nurtured with love and affection in a setting in which intimate relationships between parents and children can flourish. A rights‐based discourse is conceptually ill‐equipped to accommodate the importance of establishing and supporting caring relationships. An ethic of care, emphasizing responsibilities over rights, provides a better way of conceptualizing and responding to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Autonomy, child-rearing, and good lives.Eamonn Callan - 2004 - In David Archard (ed.), The moral and political status of children. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 118--141.
    Autonomy is important to leading a good life but a common liberal instrumental construal of the way in which it contributes to the leading of a good life is defective. A one‐sided focus on the development of capacities for revision of conceptions of the good should be corrected by attention to the value of developing capacities permitting a rational adherence to a conception of the good. Exposing children to a diverse but shallow secular and consumer culture might not facilitate goodness‐enhancing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Whose Justice? Which Rationality?Alasdair C. MacIntyre - 1988 - University of Notre Dame Press.
    [This book] develops an account of rationality and justice that is tradition specific.-http://undpress.nd.edu.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   345 citations  
  • Children's Choices or Children's Interests: Which Do Their Rights Protect?Samantha Brennan - 2004 - In David Archard & Colin M. [eds] Macleod (eds.), The moral and political status of children. Oxford University Press.
    The often‐posed dichotomy between the interest and choice theory of rights can obfuscate a proper understanding of children's rights. We need a gradualist model in which the grounds for attributing rights to a being change in response to the development of autonomy. Rights for children initially function to protect their interests but, as they develop into full‐fledged autonomous choosers, rights function to ensure that their choices, even those that do not serve their welfare, are respected.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Human flourishing: The grounds of moral judgment. [REVIEW]Allyn John Fives - 2008 - Journal of Value Inquiry 42 (2):167-185.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Children's rights and children's lives.Onora O'Neill - 1988 - Ethics 98 (3):445-463.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • (1 other version)Moral conflict and political consensus.Amy Gutmann & Dennis Thompson - 1990 - Ethics 101 (1):64-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • The insularity of the reasonable: Why political liberalism must admit the truth.David Estlund - 1998 - Ethics 108 (2):252-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Parents' rights and the value of the family.Harry Brighouse & Adam Swift - 2006 - Ethics 117 (1):80-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • (1 other version)Civic education and liberal legitimacy.Harry Brighouse - 1998 - Ethics 108 (4):719-745.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Whose Justice? Which Rationality?Alasdair Macintyre - 1988 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 23 (3):242-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   163 citations  
  • The Morality of Freedom.Ernest Marshall - 1994 - Noûs 28 (1):96-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Children: Rights and Childhood.David Archard - 1993 - Routledge.
    Whether children have rights is a debate that in recent years has spilled over into all areas of public life. It has never been more topical than now as the assumed rights of parents over their children is challenged on an almost daily basis. David Archard offers the first serious and sustained philosophical examination of children and their rights. Archard reviews arguments for and against according children rights. He concludes that every child has at least the right to the best (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Political Liberalism.J. Rawls - 1995 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 57 (3):596-598.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2283 citations  
  • Reasons, responsibility, and reliance: Replies to Wallace, Dworkin, and Deigh.T. M. Scanlon - 2002 - Ethics 112 (3):507-528.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Facing diversity: The case of epistemic abstinence.Joseph Raz - 1990 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (1):3-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Civic education and social diversity.Amy Gutmann - 1995 - Ethics 105 (3):557-579.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Whose Justice? Which Rationality?Alasdair Macintyre - 1988 - Journal of Religious Ethics 16 (2):363-363.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   395 citations  
  • Special agents: Children's autonomy and parental authority.Robert Noggle - 2004 - In David Archard (ed.), The moral and political status of children. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 97--117.
    Cognitive incompetence cannot adequately explain the special character of children's moral status. It is, in fact, because children lack preference structures that are sufficiently stable over time that they are not ’temporally extended agents’. They are best viewed as 'special agents’, and parents have the responsibility of fostering the development of temporally extended agency and other necessary related moral capacities. Parental authority should be exercised with the view to assisting children to acquire the capacities that facilitate their transition from 'special (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Value Pluralism and Communitarianism.Luke O'Sullivan - 2006 - Contemporary Political Theory 5 (4):405-427.
    Some theorists have argued recently that Berlinian value pluralism points not to liberalism, as Berlin supposed, but, in effect, to some form of communitarianism. To what extent is this true, and, to the extent that it is true, what kind of communitarianism fits best with the pluralist outlook? I argue that pluralists should acknowledge community as an important source of value and as a substantial value in itself, but they should also be prepared to question traditions and to respect values (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Whose Justice? Which Rationality?Alisdair Macintyre - 1991 - Science and Society 55 (1):106-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Value Pluralism and Communitarianism.George Crowder - 2006 - Contemporary Political Theory 5 (4):405-427.
    Some theorists have argued recently that Berlinian value pluralism points not to liberalism, as Berlin supposed, but, in effect, to some form of communitarianism. To what extent is this true, and, to the extent that it is true, what kind of communitarianism fits best with the pluralist outlook? I argue that pluralists should acknowledge community as an important source of value and as a substantial value in itself, but they should also be prepared to question traditions and to respect values (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Children.David Archard - 2003 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The Oxford handbook of practical ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Whether children have rights is a debate that in recent years has spilled over into all areas of public life. It has never been more topical than now as the assumed rights of parents over their children is challenged on an almost daily basis. David Archard offers the first serious and sustained philosophical examination of children and their rights. Archard reviews arguments for and against according children rights. He concludes that every child has at least the right to the best (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Answering Susan: Liberalism, Civic Education, and the Status of Younger Persons.Joe Coleman - 2004 - In David Archard & Colin M. [eds] Macleod (eds.), The moral and political status of children. Oxford University Press.
    While young children lack the moral powers that Rawls calls a conception of the good and a sense of justice, psychological data show that adolescents are closer to adults in this respect. The idea that civic education should be compulsory for younger person but not for adults cannot be justified by appeal to the supposed incapacities of the former. A more democratic ’participation‐oriented’ approach to the civic education of the young is more appropriate than an ’authority‐oriented’ approach. Such an approach (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The morality of freedom.J. Raz - 1986 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 178 (1):108-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   649 citations  
  • Political Liberalism and Citizenship Education: Towards Curriculum Reform.John Halliday - 1999 - British Journal of Educational Studies 47 (1):43 - 55.
    This paper is concerned with Rawls's (1993) account of an overlapping consensus and recent proposals to introduce citizenship education in parts of the UK. It is argued that both Rawls and the proposals mistake the significance and nature of such a consensus. Partly as a result of this mistake the proposals are insufficiently radical.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Democratic Education.Amy Gutmann - 1989 - Ethics 99 (2):439-441.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • Democratic Education.Amy Gutmann - 1989 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 18 (1):68-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   181 citations  
  • Reasonableness, pluralism, and liberal moral doctrines.Allyn Fives - 2010 - Journal of Value Inquiry 44 (3):321-339.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reasonable, agonistic, or good?: The character of a democrat.Allyn Fives - 2009 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 35 (8):961-983.
    Postmodernists reject what they call the universalist-rationalist framework of liberalism. When they do defend liberal democracy, they do so in a contextualist manner (within a ‘form of life’) and on the basis of contestation (‘agonism’). Liberals are right to charge postmodernism with self-contradiction, relativism, and immoralism. It is also argued in this article that liberalism and postmodernism are incompatible, and therefore, they cannot be joined together in response to the hegemonic construction of democratic debate. However, liberals are caught in a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations