Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (2 other versions)Philosophical investigations.Ludwig Wittgenstein & G. E. M. Anscombe - 1953 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 161:124-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2756 citations  
  • (1 other version)Explanation, Reduction and Empiricism.P. K. Feyerabend - 1967 - Critica 1 (2):103-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   233 citations  
  • (5 other versions)Two Dogmas of Empiricism.Willard V. O. Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):20–43.
    Modern empiricism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact, and truth which are synthetic, or grounded in fact. The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience. Both dogmas, I shall argue, are ill founded. One effect of abandoning them is, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1348 citations  
  • Carnap and logical truth.Willard van Orman Quine - 1954 - Synthese 12 (4):350--74.
    Kant's question 'How are synthetic judgments a priori possible?' pre- cipitated the Critique of Pure Reason. Question and answer notwith- standing, Mill and others persisted in doubting that such judgments were possible at all. At length some of Kant's own clearest purported.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   211 citations  
  • Approaches to reduction.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (2):137-147.
    Four current accounts of theory reduction are presented, first informally and then formally: (1) an account of direct theory reduction that is based on the contributions of Nagel, Woodger, and Quine, (2) an indirect reduction paradigm due to Kemeny and Oppenheim, (3) an "isomorphic model" schema traceable to Suppes, and (4) a theory of reduction that is based on the work of Popper, Feyerabend, and Kuhn. Reference is made, in an attempt to choose between these schemas, to the explanation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  • Implicit definition sustained.W. V. Quine - 1964 - Journal of Philosophy 61 (2):71-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • An explication of 'explication'.Joseph F. Hanna - 1968 - Philosophy of Science 35 (1):28-44.
    It is generally agreed that the method of explication consists in replacing a vague, presystematic notion (the explicandum) with a precise notion (the explicatum) formulated in a systematic context. However, Carnap and others who have used this and related terms appear to hold inconsistent views as to what constitutes an adequate explication. The central feature of the present explication of 'explication' is the correspondence condition: permitting the explicandum to deviate from some established "ordinary-language" conventions but, at the same time, requiring (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):278-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2818 citations  
  • Science and Subjectivity.Israel Scheffler - 1979 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 169 (1):119-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Logical Foundations of Probability.Rudolf Carnap - 1950 - Mind 62 (245):86-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   879 citations  
  • The comparability of scientific theories.Carl R. Kordig - 1971 - Philosophy of Science 38 (4):467-485.
    In this article I discuss the justification of scientific change and argue that it rests on different sorts of invariance. Against this background I consider notions of observation, meaning, and regulative standards. I sketch an account of the rationale of scientific change which preserves the merits and avoids the shortcomings of the approach of Feyerabend, Hanson, Kuhn, Toulmin, and others. Each of these writers would hold that transitions from one scientific tradition to another force radical changes in what is observed, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)VII.—Sentences About Believing.Roderick M. Chisholm - 1956 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56 (1):125-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • The Structure of Appearance.N. Goodman & Geoffrey Hellman - 1966 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 42 (4):828-829.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Philosophy, Science, and Method.Sidney Morgenbesser, Patrick Suppes & Morton White - 1973 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 27 (1):146-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Ontological reduction and the world of numbers.W. V. Quine - 1964 - Journal of Philosophy 61 (7):209-216.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Alternatives and incommensurables: The case of Darwin and Kelvin.J. N. Hattiangadi - 1971 - Philosophy of Science 38 (4):502-507.
    If, as it is usually understood, incommensurable theories must be compatible then one need never choose between two such theories. But if theories were incompatible and incommensurable one would have to choose between them. What if they are incompatible only outside the domain of observation? The fact that Darwin's biology can clash with Kelvin's physics (each with their respective auxiliary assumptions) regarding the age of the earth shows how commensurable theories may yet be incompatible. But it also shows that they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap.P. A. Schilpp - 1963 - Philosophy 42 (161):291-293.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • Reflections on the Unity of Science.Gerald J. Massey - 1973 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 4 (3):203-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Meaning and action.May Brodbeck - 1963 - Philosophy of Science 30 (4):309-324.
    This paper examines the current variant of the view that meaningful human actions are not amenable to causal, scientific explanation. Rather, the view examined holds that, understanding the language, we understand the meaning of other people's overt acts by analyzing the concepts appropriately applied to the situation, tracing their logical connections with other mentalistic concepts. A matter of conceptual analysis, our understanding of man is held to be a priori and necessary rather than, as with the natural sciences, a posteriori (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory.Pierre Duhem & Philip P. Wiener - 1955 - Science and Society 19 (1):85-87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   534 citations  
  • Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science.Roger C. Buck & Robert S. Cohen - 1973 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24 (3):299-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Counter-intuitivity and the method of analysis.Richard Rudner - 1950 - Philosophical Studies 1 (6):83 - 89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Vision and revolution: A postscript on Kuhn.Israel Scheffler - 1972 - Philosophy of Science 39 (3):366-374.
    In Chapter 4 of Science and Subjectivity, I offered several arguments critical of Professor Thomas Kuhn's views as expressed in his influential book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. His recent replies to these criticisms seem to me so inadequate as to suggest that he, and therefore others as well, may have failed to grasp their full import. Accordingly, I shall, in the first part of this paper, briefly recapitulate my earlier arguments and offer a short rejoinder to Professor Kuhn's replies. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Quine, synonymy and logical truth.Robert Barrett - 1965 - Philosophy of Science 32 (3/4):361-367.
    W. V. O. Quine's well-known attack upon the analytic-synthetic distinction is held to affect only one of the two species of analytic statements he distinguishes. In particular it is not directed at and does not affect the so-called logical truths. In this paper the scope of Quine's attack is extended so as to embrace the logical truths as well. It is shown that the unclarifiability of the notion of 'synonymy' deprives us not only of "analytic statements that are obtainable from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A study of radical behaviorism.Michael Scriven - 1956 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1:88-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Attribute identities in microreductions.Robert L. Causey - 1972 - Journal of Philosophy 69 (14):407-422.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Some major issues and developments in the philosophy of science of logical empiricism.Herbert Feigl - 1956 - In Herbert Feigl & Michael Scriven (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. , Vol. pp. 1--3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations