Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Completeness and Categoricity: 19th Century Axiomatics to 21st Century Senatics.Steve Awodey & Erich H. Reck - 2002 - History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (1):1-30.
    Steve Awodey and Erich H. Reck. Completeness and Categoricity: 19th Century Axiomatics to 21st Century Senatics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Completeness and Categoricity. Part I: Nineteenth-century Axiomatics to Twentieth-century Metalogic.Steve Awodey & Erich H. Reck - 2002 - History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (1):1-30.
    This paper is the first in a two-part series in which we discuss several notions of completeness for systems of mathematical axioms, with special focus on their interrelations and historical origins in the development of the axiomatic method. We argue that, both from historical and logical points of view, higher-order logic is an appropriate framework for considering such notions, and we consider some open questions in higher-order axiomatics. In addition, we indicate how one can fruitfully extend the usual set-theoretic semantics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • The Fraenkel‐Carnap question for Dedekind algebras.George Weaver & Benjamin George - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (1):92-96.
    It is shown that the second-order theory of a Dedekind algebra is categorical if it is finitely axiomatizable. This provides a partial answer to an old and neglected question of Fraenkel and Carnap: whether every finitely axiomatizable semantically complete second-order theory is categorical. It follows that the second-order theory of a Dedekind algebra is finitely axiomatizable iff the algebra is finitely characterizable. It is also shown that the second-order theory of a Dedekind algebra is quasi-finitely axiomatizable iff the algebra is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Model Theory Of Dedekind Algebras.George Weaver - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 8:135-142.
    A Dedekind algebra is an ordered pair where B is a non-empty set and h is a "similarity transformation" on B. Among the Dedekind algebras is the sequence of positive integers. Each Dedekind algebra can be decomposed into a family of disjointed, countable subalgebras which are called the configurations of the algebra. There are many isomorphic types of configurations. Each Dedekind algebra is associated with a cardinal value function called the confirmation signature which counts the number of configurations in each (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Homogeneous and universal dedekind algebras.George Weaver - 2000 - Studia Logica 64 (2):173-192.
    A Dedekind algebra is an order pair (B, h) where B is a non-empty set and h is a similarity transformation on B. Each Dedekind algebra can be decomposed into a family of disjoint, countable subalgebras called the configurations of the algebra. There are 0 isomorphism types of configurations. Each Dedekind algebra is associated with a cardinal-valued function on called its configuration signature. The configuration signature counts the number of configurations in each isomorphism type which occur in the decomposition of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Fraenkel-Carnap properties.G. Au George Weaver - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (3):285.
    In the 1920's Fraenkel and Carnap raised the question of whether or not every finitely axiomatizable semantically complete theory formulated in the theory of types is categorical. Partial answers to this and a related question are presented for theories formulated in second-order logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • From finitary to infinitary second‐order logic.George Weaver & Irena Penev - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (5):499-506.
    A back and forth condition on interpretations for those second-order languages without functional variables whose non-logical vocabulary is finite and excludes functional constants is presented. It is shown that this condition is necessary and sufficient for the interpretations to be equivalent in the language. When applied to second-order languages with an infinite non-logical vocabulary, excluding functional constants, the back and forth condition is sufficient but not necessary. It is shown that there is a class of infinitary second-order languages whose non-logical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Foundations without foundationalism: a case for second-order logic.Stewart Shapiro - 1991 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The central contention of this book is that second-order logic has a central role to play in laying the foundations of mathematics. In order to develop the argument fully, the author presents a detailed description of higher-order logic, including a comprehensive discussion of its semantics. He goes on to demonstrate the prevalence of second-order concepts in mathematics and the extent to which mathematical ideas can be formulated in higher-order logic. He also shows how first-order languages are often insufficient to codify (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   231 citations  
  • Basic Set Theory.William Mitchell - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (2):417-419.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Book Review. Basic Set Theory. Azriel Levy. [REVIEW]Harold T. Hodes - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (2):298-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Completeness and categoricty, part II: 20th century metalogic to 21st century semantics.Steve Awodey & Erich H. Reck - 2002 - History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (1):77-92.
    This paper is the second in a two-part series in which we discuss several notions of completeness for systems of mathematical axioms, with special focus on their interrelations and historical origins in the development of the axiomatic method. We argue that, both from historical and logical points of view, higher-order logic is an appropriate framework for considering such notions, and we consider some open questions in higher-order axiomatics. In addition, we indicate how one can fruitfully extend the usual set-theoretic semantics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Isomorphism and higher order equivalence.M. Ajtai - 1979 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 16 (3):181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations