Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Conceptual Revolutions.Paul Thagard - 1992 - Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    In this path-breaking work, Paul Thagard draws on history and philosophy of science, cognitive psychology, and the field of artificial intelligence to develop a ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   278 citations  
  • Moral thinking: its levels, method, and point.R. M. Hare (ed.) - 1981 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    In this work, the author has fashioned out of the logical and linguistic theses of his earlier books a full-scale but readily intelligible account of moral argument.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   341 citations  
  • The structure of empirical knowledge.Laurence BonJour - 1985 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    1 Knowledge and Justification This book is an investigation of one central problem which arises in the attempt to give a philosophical account of empirical ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   855 citations  
  • Inference to the best plan: A coherence theory of decision.P. Thagard & E. Millgram - 1997 - In P. Thagard & C. P. Shelley (eds.), [Book Chapter].
    In their introduction to this volume, Ram and Leake usefully distinguish between task goals and learning goals. Task goals are desired results or states in an external world, while learning goals are desired mental states that a learner seeks to acquire as part of the accomplishment of task goals. We agree with the fundamental claim that learning is an active and strategic process that takes place in the context of tasks and goals (see also Holland, Holyoak, Nisbett, and Thagard, 1986). (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Deliberative coherence.Elijah Millgram & Paul Thagard - 1996 - Synthese 108 (1):63 - 88.
    Choosing the right plan is often choosing the more coherent plan: but what is coherence? We argue that coherence-directed practical inference ought to be represented computationally. To that end, we advance a theory of deliberative coherence, and describe its implementation in a program modelled on Thagard's ECHO. We explain how the theory can be tested and extended, and consider its bearing on instrumentalist accounts of practical rationality.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Moral Thinking. Its Levels, Method and Point.R. M. Hare - 1983 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 37 (4):643-646.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  • Thagard’s coherentism. [REVIEW]Majid Amini - 2000 - Philosophical Books 43 (2):136-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   189 citations  
  • Ethical coherence.Paul Thagard - 1998 - Philosophical Psychology 11 (4):405 – 422.
    This paper explores the ethical relevance of a precise new characterization of coherence as maximization of satisfaction of positive and negative constraints. A coherence problem can be stated by specifying a set of elements to be accepted or rejected along with sets of positive and negative constraints that incline pairs of elements to be accepted together or rejected together. Computationally tractable and psychologically plausible algorithms are available for determining the acceptance and rejection of elements in a way that reliably approximates (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Coherence: The price of the ticket.Elijah Millgram - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (2):82-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Coherence.Elijah Millgram - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (2):82-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Reflective knowledge in the best circles.Ernest Sosa - 1997 - Journal of Philosophy 94 (8):410-430.
    According to Moore, his argument meets three conditions for being a proof: first, the premiss is different from the conclusion; second, he knows the premiss to be the case; and, third, the conclusion follows deductively.2 Further conditions may be required, but he evidently thinks his proof would satisfy these as well. As Moore is well aware, many philosophers will feel he has not given “...any satisfactory proof of the point in question."3 Some, he believes, will want the premiss itself proved. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Moral Thinking. Its Levels, Method and Point.R. M. Hare - 1985 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 90 (2):271-273.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   152 citations  
  • Computing coherence.P. Thagard - 1992 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15:485-488.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mental Leaps: Analogy in Creative Thought.Keith J. Holyoak & Paul Thagard - 1995 - MIT Press.
    Keith Holyoak and Paul Thagard provide a unified, comprehensive account of the diverse operations and applications of analogy, including problem solving, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • Reflective Knowledge in the Best Circles.Ernest Sosa - 1997 - Journal of Philosophy 94 (8):410.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • 33. reflective knowledge in the best circles.Ernest Sosa - 2003 - In Steven Luper (ed.), Essential Knowledge: Readings in Epistemology. Longman. pp. 324.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Copernicus, Ptolemy, and explanatory coherence.G. Nowak & P. Thagard - 1992 - In R. Giere & H. Feigl (eds.), Cognitive Models of Science. University of Minnesota Press. pp. pp. 274-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations