Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Role of Good Upbringing in Aristotle’s Ethics.Iakovos Vasiliou - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (4):771-797.
    It is argued that a proper appreciation of the passages in the Nicomachean Ethics where Aristotle requires the student of ethics to be well brought up implies that the Ethics is not attempting to justify the objective correctness of its substantive conception of happiness to someone who does not already appreciate its distinctive value. Reflection on the import of the good-upbringing restriction can lead us to see that Aristotle's conception of ethical objectivity is not only radically different from modern moral (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • (1 other version)Contemplation, the Noble, and the Mean: The Standard of Moral Virtue in Aristotle's Ethics.Thomas Tuozzo - 1995 - Apeiron 28 (4):129-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle on Becoming Virtuous by Doing Virtuous Actions.Marta Jimenez - 2016 - Phronesis 61 (1):3-32.
    Aristotle ’s claim that we become virtuous by doing virtuous actions raises a familiar problem: How can we perform virtuous actions unless we are already virtuous? I reject deflationary accounts of the answer given in _Nicomachean Ethics_ 2.4 and argue instead that proper habituation involves doing virtuous actions with the right motive, i.e. for the sake of the noble, even though learners do not yet have virtuous dispositions. My interpretation confers continuity to habituation and explains in a non-mysterious way how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Aristotle on “Steering the Young by Pleasure and Pain”.Marta Jimenez - 2015 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 29 (2):137-164.
    At least since Burnyeat’s “Aristotle on Learning to Be Good,” one of the most popular ways of explaining moral development in Aristotle is by appealing to mechanisms of pleasure and pain. Aristotle himself suggests this kind of explanation when he says that “in educating the young we steer them by the rudders of pleasure and pain” (Nicomachean Ethics X.1, 1172a21). However, I argue that, contrary to the dominant view, Aristotle’s view on moral development in the Nicomachean Ethics is not mainly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)After Virtue.A. MacIntyre - 1981 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 46 (1):169-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1810 citations  
  • Aristotle on learning to be good.Myles Burnyeat - 1980 - In Amélie Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle's Ethics. University of California Press. pp. 69–92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   182 citations  
  • Aristotle on the apparent good: perception, phantasia, thought, and desire.Jessica Moss - 2012 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Pt. I. The apparent good. Evaluative cognition -- Perceiving the good -- Phantasia and the apparent good -- pt. II. The apparent good and non-rational motivation. Passions and the apparent good -- Akrasia and the apparent good -- pt. III. The apparent good and rational motivation. Phantasia and deliberation -- Happiness, virtue, and the apparent good -- Practical induction -- Conclusion : Aristotle's practical empiricism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Conception of Τò Καλόυ.Kelly Rogers - 1993 - Ancient Philosophy 13 (2):355.
    All the virtues, Aristotle says, are undertaken for the sake of the noble ("to kalon"). Curiously, however, he offers no direct account of this concept, despite its role as the end ("telos") of virtue. Fortunately, two patterns of usage in Aristotle's ethical discourse offer a means to clarification. Aristotle is found to link nobility jointly with his conceptions of appropriateness and praiseworthiness. An examination of these usage- patterns is found not only to elucidate Aristotle's view of nobility, moreover, but to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Why does Aristotle Think that Ethical Virtue is Required for Practical Wisdom?Ursula Coope - 2012 - Phronesis 57 (2):142-163.
    Abstract In this paper, I ask why Aristotle thinks that ethical virtue (rather than mere self-control) is required for practical wisdom. I argue that a satisfactory answer will need to explain why being prone to bad appetites implies a failing of the rational part of the soul. I go on to claim that the self-controlled person does suffer from such a rational failing: a failure to take a specifically rational kind of pleasure in fine action. However, this still leaves a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Some Remarks on Aristotle’s Moral Psychology.John M. Cooper - 1989 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 (S1):25-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Ethics with Aristotle.Sarah Broadie - 1991 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this incisive study Sarah Broadie gives an argued account of the main topics of Aristotle's ethics: eudaimonia, virtue, voluntary agency, practical reason, akrasia, pleasure, and the ethical status of theoria. She explores the sense of "eudaimonia," probes Aristotle's division of the soul and its virtues, and traces the ambiguities in "voluntary." Fresh light is shed on his comparison of practical wisdom with other kinds of knowledge, and a realistic account is developed of Aristototelian deliberation. The concept of pleasure as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   178 citations  
  • Eudaimonia, external results, and choosing virtuous actions for themselves.Jennifer Whiting - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):270-290.
    Aristotle's requirement that virtuous actions be chosen for themselves is typically interpreted, in Kantian terms, as taking virtuous action to have intrinsic rather than consequentialist value. This raises problems about how to reconcile Aristotle's requirement with (a) the fact that virtuous actions typically aim at ends beyond themselves (usually benefits to others); and (b) Aristotle's apparent requirement that everything (including virtuous action) be chosen for the sake of eudaimonia. I offer an alternative interpretation, based on Aristotle's account of loving a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Ethics of Aristotle.Alexander Aristotle & Grant - 1857 - John W. Parker and Son.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • 5. Aristotle on Learning to Be Good.M. F. Burnyeat - 1980 - In Amélie Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle's Ethics. University of California Press. pp. 69-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Acting virtuously as an end in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics.Sukaina Hirji - 2018 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (6):1006-1026.
    Sometimes, in the Nicomachean Ethics (NE), Aristotle describes virtuous actions as the sorts of actions that are ends; it is important for Aristotle to do so if he wants to maintain, as he seems to at least until NE 10.7-8, that virtuous actions are a constituent of eudaimonia. At other times, he claims that virtuous actions are the sorts of actions that are for the sake of ends beyond themselves; after all, no one would choose to go into battle or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Ethical Theory.W. F. R. Hardie & J. Donald Monan - 1968 - Ethics 80 (1):76-82.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Harmonia, Melos and Rhytmos. Aristotle on Musical Education.Elena Cagnoli Fiecconi - 2016 - Ancient Philosophy 36 (2):409-424.
    In this paper, I reconstruct the reasons why Aristotle thinks that musical education is important for moral education. Musical education teaches us to enjoy appropriately and to recognize perceptually fine melodies and rhythms. Fine melodies and rhythms are similar to the kind of movements fine actions consist in and fine characters display. By teaching us to enjoy and recognise fine melodies and rhythms, musical education can train us to recognize and to take pleasure in fine actions and characters. Thus, musical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)VII*—Aristotle On the Rôle of Intellect in Virtue.Richard Sorabji - 1974 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74 (1):107-129.
    Richard Sorabji; VII*—Aristotle On the Rôle of Intellect in Virtue, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 74, Issue 1, 1 June 1974, Pages 107–129, htt.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Aristotle.David Charles - 1995 - In Ted Honderich (ed.), The Philosophers: Introducing Great Western Thinkers. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • From Duty and for the Sake of the Noble: Kant and Aristotle on Morally Good Action.Christine M. Korsgaard - 1996 - In Stephen Engstrom & Jennifer Whiting (eds.), Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty. Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle believes that an agent lacks virtue unless she enjoys the performance of virtuous actions, while Kant claims that the person who does her duty despite contrary inclinations exhibits a moral worth that the person who acts from inclination lacks. Despite these differences, this chapter argues that Aristotle and Kant share a distinctive view of the object of human choice and locus of moral value: that what we choose, and what has moral value, are not mere acts, but actions: acts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Imitating Virtue.Margaret Hampson - 2019 - Phronesis 64 (3):292-320.
    Moral virtue is, for Aristotle, famously acquired through the practice of virtuous actions. But how should we understand the activity of Aristotle’s moral learner, and how does her activity result in the acquisition of virtue? I argue that by understanding Aristotle’s learner as engaged in the emulative imitation of a virtuous agent, we can best account for her development. Such activity crucially involves the adoption of the virtuous agent’s perspective, from which I argue the learner is positioned so as to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (1 other version)Acting as the virtuous person acts.Bernard Williams - 1995 - In Robert Heinaman (ed.), Aristotle and Moral Realism. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press. pp. 13--23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Moral habituation.Rosalind Hursthouse - 1988 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 6:201-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Aristotle, the Nicomachean ethics: a commentary.Harold Henry Joachim - 1951 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press. Edited by D. A. Rees.
    An edited collection of lectures delivered by the late H. H. Joachim on the subject of Aristotle's Nichomachean Ethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Friendship and the good in Aristotle.John M. Cooper - 1977 - Philosophical Review 86 (3):290-315.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Theory of Moral Insight.T. Engberg-Pedersen - 1983 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 47 (2):312-313.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Aristotle: The Desire to Understand.Jonathan Lear - 1988 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This is a 1988 philosophical introduction to Aristotle, and Professor Lear starts where Aristotle himself starts. The first sentence of the Metaphysics states that all human beings by their nature desire to know. But what is it for us to be animated by this desire in this world? What is it for a creature to have a nature; what is our human nature; what must the world be like to be intelligible; and what must we be like to understand it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • The Pleasures of Reason in Plato, Aristotle, and the Hellenistic Hedonists.James Warren - 2014 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Human lives are full of pleasures and pains. And humans are creatures that are able to think: to learn, understand, remember and recall, plan and anticipate. Ancient philosophers were interested in both of these facts and, what is more, were interested in how these two facts are related to one another. There appear to be, after all, pleasures and pains associated with learning and inquiring, recollecting and anticipating. We enjoy finding something out. We are pained to discover that a belief (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Chapter Five.Terence H. Irwin - 1985 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 1 (1):115-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Desirability of Friends.Aryeh Kosman - 2004 - Ancient Philosophy 24 (1):135-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Aristotle: The Nicomachean Ethics. A commentary by the late H. H. JOACHIM. By Charles Wegener.H. H. Joachim & D. A. Rees - 1951 - Ethics 62 (4):300-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotelis Ethica Nicomachea.Ingram Bywater (ed.) - 1890 - Cambridge University Press.
    Ingram Bywater first published his edition of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics in 1890. His reconstruction of the Greek text is based on a careful weighing of the Greek manuscript evidence, Latin translations, the witness of early commentators and his own thorough knowledge of Aristotle's language and style. Bywater's choice of readings introduced many important alterations to the text given in previous editions; his preference for manuscripts Kb and Lb and for the commentary of Aspasius, represented by Heylbut's edition, explains many of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Aristotle on Improving One's Character.Gianluca di Muzio - 2000 - Phronesis 45 (3):205 - 219.
    Contrary to what most interpreters hold, in the "Nicomachean Ethics" Aristotle is not committed to the view that people of established vicious character could never become good. The present paper proves this result (1) by giving a better reading of 1114 a 12-21, a passage which has traditionally been taken to assert that unjust and self-indulgent people are doomed to a lifetime of vice; (2) by showing that when Aristotle refers to self-indulgent people as "incurable", he does not mean that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Moral Motivation: A History.Iakovos Vasiliou (ed.) - 2016 - New York: Oxford University Press USA.
    Moral Motivation presents a history of the concept of moral motivation. The book consists of ten chapters by eminent scholars in the history of philosophy, covering Plato, Aristotle, later Peripatetic philosophy, medieval philosophy, Spinoza, Locke, Hume, Kant, Fichte and Hegel, and the consequentialist tradition. In addition, four interdisciplinary "Reflections" discuss how the topic of moral motivation arises in epic poetry, Cicero, early opera, and Theodore Dreiser. Most contemporary philosophical discussions of moral motivation focus on whether and how moral beliefs by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics (367-323 BC).T. H. Irwin - 2003 - In Jorge J. E. Gracia, Gregory M. Reichberg & Bernard N. Schumacher (eds.), The Classics of Western Philosophy: A Reader's Guide. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Reason, moral virtue, and moral value'.John Cooper - 1996 - In Michael Frede & Gisela Striker (eds.), Rationality in Greek thought. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 81--114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Aristotle: The Desire to Understand.Richard Kraut & Jonathan Lear - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (3):522.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations