Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Moral Magic of Consent: Heidi M. Hurd.Heidi Hurd - 1996 - Legal Theory 2 (2):121-146.
    We regularly wield powers that, upon close scrutiny, appear remarkably magical. By sheer exercise of will, we bring into existence things that have never existed before. With but a nod, we effect the disappearance of things that have long served as barriers to the actions of others. And, by mere resolve, we generate things that pose significant obstacles to others' exercise of liberty. What is the nature of these things that we create and destroy by our mere decision to do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • The Theory and Practice of Autonomy.Gerald Dworkin - 1988 - Philosophy 64 (250):571-572.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   405 citations  
  • Paternalistic Laws.Alan H. Goldman & Michael N. Goldman - 1990 - Philosophical Topics 18 (1):65-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mill Versus Paternalism.Richard J. Arneson - 1979 - Philosophy Research Archives 5:89-119.
    This paper attempts a defense of John Stuart Mill’s absolute ban against paternalistic restrictions on liberty. Mill’s principle looks more credible once we recognize that some instances of what are thought to be justified instances of paternalism are not instances of paternalism at all—e.g. anti-duelling laws. An interpretation of Mill’s argument is advanced which stresses his commitment to autonomy and his suggestion that exactly the same reasons which favor absolute freedom of speech also favor an absolute prohibition of paternalism. Alternative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • A Defense of Abortion.David Boonin - 2002 - Cambridge University Press.
    David Boonin has written the most thorough and detailed case for the moral permissibility of abortion yet published. Critically examining a wide range of arguments that attempt to prove that every human fetus has a right to life, he shows that each of these arguments fails on its own terms. He then explains how even if the fetus does have a right to life, abortion can still be shown to be morally permissible on the critique of abortion's own terms. Finally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • The Theory and Practice of Autonomy.Gerald Dworkin - 1988 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This important new book develops a new concept of autonomy. The notion of autonomy has emerged as central to contemporary moral and political philosophy, particularly in the area of applied ethics. professor Dworkin examines the nature and value of autonomy and uses the concept to analyse various practical moral issues such as proxy consent in the medical context, paternalism, and entrapment by law enforcement officials.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   314 citations  
  • Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation.Seana Valentine Shiffrin - 2000 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 29 (3):205-250.
    The unconscionability doctrine in contract law enables a court to decline to enforce a contract whose terms are seriously one-sided, exploitative, or otherwise manifestly unfair. It is often criticized for being paternalist. The essay argues that the characterization of unconscionability doctrine as paternalist reflects common but misleading thought about paternalism and obscures more important issues about autonomy and social connection. The defense responds to another criticism: that unconscionability doctrine is an inappropriate, because economically inefficient, egalitarian tool. The final part discusses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations  
  • Paternalism.Gerald Dworkin - 1972 - The Monist 56 (1):64-84.
    I take as my starting point the “one very simple principle” proclaimed by Mill in On Liberty … “That principle is, that the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. He cannot rightfully be compelled to do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  • Mill, Paternalism, and Slavery.John D. Hodson - 1980 - Analysis 41 (1):60 - 62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Paternalism and Public Policy.Bill New - 1999 - Economics and Philosophy 15 (1):63.
    Wherever a government or state is concerned with the welfare of its citizens, there will probably also exist policies which compel the individual citizen to undertake or abstain from activities which affect that citizen alone. The set of theories behind such policies is collectively known as ‘paternalism’. It is not hard to understand why this term has developed strong pejorative overtones. Policies of this type appear to offend a fundamental tenet of liberal societies: namely, that the individual is best placed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Paternalistic Laws.Alan H. Goldman & Michael N. Goldman - 1990 - Philosophical Topics 18 (1):65-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • In defense of hard paternalism.Danny Scoccia - 2008 - Law and Philosophy 27 (4):351 - 381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Joel Feinberg and the justification of hard paternalism.Richard J. Arneson - 2005 - Legal Theory 11 (3):259-284.
    Joel Feinberg was a brilliant philosopher whose work in social and moral philosophy is a legacy of excellent, even stunning achievement. Perhaps his most memorable achievement is his four-volume treatise on The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, and perhaps the most striking jewel in this crowning achievement is his passionate and deeply insightful treatment of paternalism.1 Feinberg opposes Legal Paternalism, the doctrine that “it is always a good reason in support of a [criminal law] prohibition that it is necessary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Rational Desires and the Limitation of Life‐Sustaining Treatment.Julian Savulescu - 2007 - Bioethics 8 (3):191-222.
    ABSTRACT It is accepted that treatment of previously competent, now incompetent patients can be limited if that is what the patient would desire, if she were now competent. Expressed past preferences or an advance directive are often taken to constitute sufficient evidence of what a patient would now desire. I distinguish between desires and rational desires. I argue that for a desire to be an expression of a person's autonomy, it must be or satisfy that person's rational desires. A person (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Paternalism and Consent.Douglas Husak - 2015 - In Thomas Schramme (ed.), New Perspectives on Paternalism and Health Care. Cham: Springer Verlag.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Harm to Self.Joel Feinberg - 1986 - Oxford University Press USA.
    This is the third volume of Joel Feinberg's highly regarded The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, a four-volume series in which Feinberg skillfully addresses a complex question: What kinds of conduct may the state make criminal without infringing on the moral autonomy of individual citizens? In Harm to Self, Feinberg offers insightful commentary into various notions attached to self-inflicted harm, covering such topics as legal paternalism, personal sovereignty and its boundaries, voluntariness and assumptions of risk, consent and its counterfeits, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • Coercion.Alan Wertheimer - 1990 - Princeton University Press.
    These paperback editions preserve the original texts of these important books while presenting them in durable paperback editions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Consent and the Problem of Framing Effects.Jason Hanna - 2011 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 14 (5):517-531.
    Our decision-making is often subject to framing effects: alternative but equally informative descriptions of the same options elicit different choices. When a decision-maker is vulnerable to framing, she may consent under one description of the act, which suggests that she has waived her right, yet be disposed to dissent under an equally informative description of the act, which suggests that she has not waived her right. I argue that in such a case the decision-maker’s consent is simply irrelevant to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Paternalism.Gerald Dworkin - 1972 - The Monist.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • Enhancing autonomy in paid surrogacy.Jennifer Damelio & Kelly Sorensen - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (5):269–277.
    The gestational surrogate – and her economic and educational vulnerability in particular – is the focus of many of the most persistent worries about paid surrogacy. Those who employ her, and those who broker and organize her services, usually have an advantage over her in resources and information. That asymmetry exposes her to the possibility of exploitation and abuse. Accordingly, some argue for banning paid surrogacy. Others defend legal permission on grounds of surrogate autonomy, but often retain concerns about the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Mill versus paternalism.Richard J. Arneson - 1980 - Ethics 90 (4):470-489.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Paternalistic Intervention: The Moral Bounds on Benevolence.Donald Vandeveer - 1986 - Princeton University Press.
    Donald VanDeVeer probes the moral complexities of the question: under what conditions is it permissible to intervene invasively in the lives of competent persons--for example, by deception, force, or coercive threat--for their own good? In a work with broad significance for law, public policy, professional-client relations, and private interactions, he presents a theory of an autonomy-respecting" paternalism. Originally published in 1986. The Princeton Legacy Library uses the latest print-on-demand technology to again make available previously out-of-print books from the distinguished backlist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Liberalism and Prostitution.Peter de Marneffe - 2009 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Civil libertarians characterize prostitution as a "victimless crime," and argue that it ought to be legalized. Feminist critics counter that prostitution is not victimless, since it harms the people who do it. Civil libertarians respond that most women freely choose to do this work, and that it is paternalistic for the government to limit a person's liberty for her own good. In this book Peter de Marneffe argues that although most prostitution is voluntary, paternalistic prostitution laws in some form are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Taking Liberties.David Zimmerman - 2002 - Social Theory and Practice 28 (4):577-609.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Physician-Assisted Suicide, Disability, and Paternalism.Danny Scoccia - 2010 - Social Theory and Practice 36 (3):479-498.
    Some disability rights (DR) advocates oppose physician-assisted suicide (PAS) laws like Oregon’s on the grounds that they reflect ableist prejudice: how else can their limit on PAS eligibility to the terminally ill be explained? The paper answers this DR objection. It concedes that the limit in question cannot be defended on soft paternalist grounds, and offers a hard paternalist defense of it. The DR objection makes two mistakes: it overlooks the possibility of a hard paternalist defense of the limit, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Coercion.Alan Wertheimer - 1989 - Ethics 99 (3):642-644.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • Paternalism.Rolf Sartorius - 1983 - Ethics 95 (2):353-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Paternalism and Impairment.Jason Hanna - 2011 - Social Theory and Practice 37 (3):434-460.
    Most opponents of paternalism agree that autonomy does not protect substantially impaired choices. Yet this common anti-paternalist view faces serious problems. First, I argue that it threatens to justify nearly all beneficial intervention, since all imprudent choices are impaired. Attempts to avoid this problem yield other implications that anti-paternalists would reject. Second, I argue that anti-paternalists have no convincing way of showing that impaired choices, such as those produced by emotional distress, are not protected by autonomy. In light of these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Self-ownership and paternalism.Steven Wall - 2009 - Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (4):399-417.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Paternalism and respect for autonomy.Danny Scoccia - 1990 - Ethics 100 (2):318-334.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Paternalistic behavior.Bernard Gert & Charles M. Culver - 1976 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (1):45-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Taking Liberties.David Zimmerman - 2002 - Social Theory and Practice 28 (4):577-609.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Feinberg's anti-paternalism and the balancing strategy.Heidi Malm - 2005 - Legal Theory 11 (3):193-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Paternalism and Biobehavioral Control.Tom L. Beauchamp - 1977 - The Monist 60 (1):62-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Paternalism and cognitive bias.J. D. Trout - 2004 - Law and Philosophy 24 (4):393-434.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • For our own good.David Archard - 1994 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72 (3):283 – 293.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • "Paternalism" and Social Policy.Edward Sankowski - 1985 - American Philosophical Quarterly 22 (1):1 - 12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Principle of Paternalism.John D. Hodson - 1977 - American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1):61 - 69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations