Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. On inductive logic.Rudolf Carnap - 1945 - Philosophy of Science 12 (2):72-97.
    Among the various meanings in which the word ‘probability’ is used in everyday language, in the discussion of scientists, and in the theories of probability, there are especially two which must be clearly distinguished. We shall use for them the terms ‘probability1’ and ‘probability2'. Probability1 is a logical concept, a certain logical relation between two sentences ; it is the same as the concept of degree of confirmation. I shall write briefly “c” for “degree of confirmation,” and “c” for “the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • From Classical to Intuitionistic Probability.Brian Weatherson - 2003 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 44 (2):111-123.
    We generalize the Kolmogorov axioms for probability calculus to obtain conditions defining, for any given logic, a class of probability functions relative to that logic, coinciding with the standard probability functions in the special case of classical logic but allowing consideration of other classes of "essentially Kolmogorovian" probability functions relative to other logics. We take a broad view of the Bayesian approach as dictating inter alia that from the perspective of a given logic, rational degrees of belief are those representable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Induction and hypothesis.Stephen Francis Barker - 1957 - Ithaca, N.Y.,: Cornell University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Inductive simplicity.Robert Ackermann - 1961 - Philosophy of Science 28 (2):152-161.
    The fact that simplicity has been linked with induction by many philosophers of science, some of whom have proposed or supported criteria of “inductive simplicity,” means that the problem must be given some serious attention. I take “inductive simplicity” as a title, however, only by way of concession to these historical treatments, since it is precisely the burden of my paper to show that there is no such thing. So much for the conclusion. I shall spend the remainder of my (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • What conditional probability could not be.Alan Hájek - 2003 - Synthese 137 (3):273--323.
    Kolmogorov''s axiomatization of probability includes the familiarratio formula for conditional probability: 0).$$ " align="middle" border="0">.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   309 citations  
  • The special theory of relativity.David Bohm - 1965 - New York,: W.A. Benjamin.
    With clarity and grace, he also reveals the limited truth of some of the "common sense" assumptions which make it difficult for us to appreciate its full ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The Special Theory of Relativity.David Bohm - 1965 - New York,: Routledge.
    In these inspiring lectures David Bohm explores Albert Einstein’s celebrated _Theory of Relativity_ that transformed forever the way we think about time and space. Yet for Bohm the implications of the theory were far more revolutionary both in scope and impact even than this. Stepping back from dense theoretical and scientific detail in this eye-opening work, Bohm describes how the notion of relativity strikes at the heart of our very conception of the universe, regardless of whether we are physicists or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • .Stephen Makin (ed.) - 2006 - Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Fine-grained opinion, probability, and the logic of full belief.Bas C. van Fraassen - 1995 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 24 (4):349-377.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Likelihood and convergence.Elliott Sober - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (2):228-237.
    A common view among statisticians is that convergence (which statisticians call consistency) is a necessary property of an inference rule or estimator. In this paper, this view is challenged by appeal to an example in which a rule of inference has a likelihood rationale but is not convergent. The example helps clarify the significance of the likelihood concept in statistical inference.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Back to Aristotle!Hartley Slater - 2011 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 20 (4):275-283.
    There were already confusions in the Middle Ages with the reading of Aristotle on negative terms, and removing these confusions shows that the four traditional Syllogistic forms of statement can be readily generalised not only to handle polyadic relations (for long a source of difficulty), but even other, more measured quantifiers than just ‘all’, ‘some’, and ‘no’. But these historic confusions merely supplement the main confusions, which arose in more modern times, regarding the logic of singular statements. These main confusions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reasoning About Uncertain Conditionals.Niki Pfeifer - 2014 - Studia Logica 102 (4):849-866.
    There is a long tradition in formal epistemology and in the psychology of reasoning to investigate indicative conditionals. In psychology, the propositional calculus was taken for granted to be the normative standard of reference. Experimental tasks, evaluation of the participants’ responses and psychological model building, were inspired by the semantics of the material conditional. Recent empirical work on indicative conditionals focuses on uncertainty. Consequently, the normative standard of reference has changed. I argue why neither logic nor standard probability theory provide (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Aristotle on Modality, I.Stephen Makin & Nicholas Denyer - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (1):143-161.
    Aristotle draws two sets of distinctions in Metaphysics 9.2, first between non-rational and rational capacities, and second between one way and two way capacities. He then argues for three claims: [A] if a capacity is rational, then it is a two way capacity [B] if a capacity is non-rational, then it is a one way capacity [C] a two way capacity is not indifferently related to the opposed outcomes to which it can give rise I provide explanations of Aristotle's terminology, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic.David Lewis - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (5):113-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   510 citations  
  • A defense of imprecise credences in inference and decision making1.James M. Joyce - 2010 - Philosophical Perspectives 24 (1):281-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   163 citations  
  • The measurement of simplicity.Donald J. Hillman - 1962 - Philosophy of Science 29 (3):225-252.
    Various formulations of the principle of simplicity in science are examined and rejected in favor of Goodman's proposal, the essence of which is to concentrate attention upon the predicates that form the extralogical basis of any given theory and to provide measures for comparing the relative structural simplicity of different sets of such predicates. The postulational basis of Goodman's method is set out and explained, together with some important amendments and additions, and a number of theorems are proved, with whose (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Right Square.Hartley Slater - 2012 - In J.-Y. Beziau & Dale Jacquette (eds.), Around and Beyond the Square of Opposition. Birkhäuser. pp. 139--145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Potentiality and Virtuality.Quentin Meillassoux - 2007 - Collapse 2:55-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • An Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method.Morris R. Cohen & Ernest Nagel - 1936 - Philosophy 11 (42):219-221.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Induction and Hypothesis.S. F. Barker - 1960 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 11 (42):164-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • On the Use of Likelihood as a Guide to Truth.Steven Orla Kimbrough - 1980 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1980:117 - 128.
    Confirmation functions are generally thought of as probability functions. The well known difficulties associated with the probabilistic confirmation functions proposed to date indicate that functions other than probability functions should be investigated for the purpose of developing an adequate basis for confirmation theory. This paper deals with one such function, the likelihood function. First, it is argued here that likelihood is not a probability function. Second, a proof is given that, in the limit, likelihood can be used to determine which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation