Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Intentional Stance.[author unknown] - 1987 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 52 (2):350-351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • The Intentional Stance.Daniel Clement Dennett - 1981 - MIT Press.
    Through the use of such "folk" concepts as belief, desire, intention, and expectation, Daniel Dennett asserts in this first full scale presentation of...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1498 citations  
  • Sincere, Deceitful, and Ironic Communicative Acts and the Role of the Theory of Mind in Childhood.Francesca M. Bosco & Ilaria Gabbatore - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Pragmatics, Modularity and Mind‐reading.Dan Sperber & Deirdre Wilson - 2002 - Mind and Language 17 (1-2):3–23.
    The central problem for pragmatics is that sentence meaning vastly underdetermines speaker’s meaning. The goal of pragmatics is to explain how the gap between sentence meaning and speaker’s meaning is bridged. This paper defends the broadly Gricean view that pragmatic interpretation is ultimately an exercise in mind-reading, involving the inferential attribution of intentions. We argue, however, that the interpretation process does not simply consist in applying general mind-reading abilities to a particular (communicative) domain. Rather, it involves a dedicated comprehension module, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   152 citations  
  • Pragmatics.Dan Sperber & Deirdre Wilson - 1981 - Cognition 10 (1-3):281-286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Comprehension and Hemispheric Processing of Irony in Schizophrenia.Ronit Saban-Bezalel & Nira Mashal - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind?David Premack & G. Woodruff - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):515-629.
    An individual has a theory of mind if he imputes mental states to himself and others. A system of inferences of this kind is properly viewed as a theory because such states are not directly observable, and the system can be used to make predictions about the behavior of others. As to the mental states the chimpanzee may infer, consider those inferred by our own species, for example, purpose or intention, as well as knowledge, belief, thinking, doubt, guessing, pretending, liking, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1124 citations  
  • Mindreading and verbal communication.Anna Papafragou - 2002 - Mind and Language 17 (1-2):55–67.
    The idea that verbal communication involves a species of mindreading is not new. Among linguists and philosophers, largely as a result of Grice’s (1957, 1967) influence, it has long been recognized that the act of communicating involves on the part of the communicator and the addressee mutual metarepresentations of each others’ mental states. In psychology, the coordination of common ground and attention in conversation has been pursued in a variety of studies (e.g. Clark and Marshall, 1981; Bruner, 1983).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Understanding Minds and Understanding Communicated Meanings in Schizophrenia.Robyn Langdon, Martin Davies & Max Coltheart - 2002 - Mind and Language 17 (1‐2):68-104.
    The work reported in this paper investigated the putative functional dependence of pragmatic language skills on general mind‐reading capacity by testing theory‐of‐mind abilities and understanding of non‐literal speech in patients with schizophrenia and in healthy controls. Patients showed difficulties with inferring mental states on a false‐belief picture‐sequencing task and with understanding metaphors and irony on a story‐comprehension task. These difficulties were independent of low verbal IQ and a more generalised problem inhibiting prepotent information. Understanding of metaphors and understanding of irony (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Intentional Stance.Patricia Kitcher - 1990 - Philosophical Review 99 (1):126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Communicative competence and theory of mind in autism: A test of relevance theory.Francesca G. E. Happé - 1993 - Cognition 48 (2):101-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • Relevance: Communication and Cognition.Dan Sperber & Deirdre Wilson - 1986/1995 - Oxford: Blackwell.
    This revised edition includes a new Preface outlining developments in Relevance Theory since 1986, discussing the more serious criticisms of the theory, and ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1175 citations  
  • Pragmatics.S. C. Levinson - 1983 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 49 (3):531-532.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   531 citations  
  • Before and below 'theory of mind': embodied simulation and the neural correlates of social cognition.Vittorio Gallese - 2007 - In Nathan Emery, Nicola Clayton & Chris Frith (eds.), Social Intelligence: From Brain to Culture. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Pragmatics.Dan Sperber & Deirder Wilson - 2005 - In Frank Jackson & Michael Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Before and below 'theory of mind': Embodied simulation and the neural correlates of social cognition.Vittorio Gallese - 2007 - Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B-Biological Sciences 362 (1480):659-669.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Apraxia, metaphor and mirror neurons.V. S. Ramachandran - unknown
    Summary Ideomotor apraxia is a cognitive disorder in which the patient loses the ability to accurately perform learned, skilled actions. This is despite normal limb power and coordination. It has long been known that left supramarginal gyrus lesions cause bilateral upper limb apraxia and it was proposed that this area stored a visualkinaesthetic image of the skilled action, which was translated elsewhere in the brain into the pre-requisite movement formula. We hypothesise that, rather than these two functions occurring separately, both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations