Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Ideas and Results in Proof Theory.Dag Prawitz & J. E. Fenstad - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (2):232-234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   145 citations  
  • Methoden zur Axiomatisierung beliebiger Aussagen‐ und Prädikatenkalküle.Karl Schröter - 1955 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 1 (4):241-251.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Logical Pluralism, Meaning-Variance, and Verbal Disputes.Ole Thomassen Hjortland - 2013 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (2):355-373.
    Logical pluralism has been in vogue since JC Beall and Greg Restall 2006 articulated and defended a new pluralist thesis. Recent criticisms such as Priest 2006a and Field 2009 have suggested that there is a relationship between their type of logical pluralism and the meaning-variance thesis for logic. This is the claim, often associated with Quine 1970, that a change of logic entails a change of meaning. Here we explore the connection between logical pluralism and meaning-variance, both in general and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Harmony, Purity, Simplicity and a “Seemingly Magical Fact”.Peter Milne - 2002 - The Monist 85 (4):498-534.
    In his penetrating and thought-provoking article “What Is Logic?” Ian Hacking flags an issue that he leaves undiscussed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Natural Semantics: Why Natural Deduction is Intuitionistic.James W. Garson - 2001 - Theoria 67 (2):114-139.
    In this paper investigates how natural deduction rules define connective meaning by presenting a new method for reading semantical conditions from rules called natural semantics. Natural semantics explains why the natural deduction rules are profoundly intuitionistic. Rules for conjunction, implication, disjunction and equivalence all express intuitionistic rather than classical truth conditions. Furthermore, standard rules for negation violate essential conservation requirements for having a natural semantics. The standard rules simply do not assign a meaning to the negation sign. Intuitionistic negation fares (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Roundabout the Runabout Inference-Ticket.J. T. Stevenson - 1960 - Analysis 21 (6):124-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Knowledge by deduction.Ian Rumfitt - 2008 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 77 (1):61-84.
    It seems beyond doubt that a thinker can come to know a conclusion by deducing it from premisses that he knows already, but philosophers have found it puzzling how a thinker could acquire knowledge in this way. Assuming a broadly externalist conception of knowledge, I explain why judgements competently deduced from known premisses are themselves knowledgeable. Assuming an exclusionary conception of judgeable content, I further explain how such judgements can be informative. (According to the exclusionary conception, which I develop from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • On The Sense and Reference of A Logical Constant.Harold Hodes - 2004 - Philosophical Quarterly 54 (214):134-165.
    Logicism is, roughly speaking, the doctrine that mathematics is fancy logic. So getting clear about the nature of logic is a necessary step in an assessment of logicism. Logic is the study of logical concepts, how they are expressed in languages, their semantic values, and the relationships between these things and the rest of our concepts, linguistic expressions, and their semantic values. A logical concept is what can be expressed by a logical constant in a language. So the question “What (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • ‘Yes’, ‘no’ and ‘can't say’.Michael Dummett - 2002 - Mind 111 (442):289-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Rejection.Timothy Smiley - 1996 - Analysis 56 (1):1–9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  • Outline of a theory of truth.Saul Kripke - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (19):690-716.
    A formal theory of truth, alternative to tarski's 'orthodox' theory, based on truth-value gaps, is presented. the theory is proposed as a fairly plausible model for natural language and as one which allows rigorous definitions to be given for various intuitive concepts, such as those of 'grounded' and 'paradoxical' sentences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   882 citations  
  • Completeness and super-valuations.Gary M. Hardegree - 2005 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (1):81 - 95.
    This paper uses the notion of Galois-connection to examine the relation between valuation-spaces and logics. Every valuation-space gives rise to a logic, and every logic gives rise to a valuation space, where the resulting pair of functions form a Galois-connection, and the composite functions are closure-operators. A valuation-space (resp., logic) is said to be complete precisely if it is Galois-closed. Two theorems are proven. A logic is complete if and only if it is reflexive and transitive. A valuation-space is complete (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • On sequence-conclusion natural deduction systems.Branislav R. Boričić - 1985 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 14 (4):359 - 377.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Classical harmony.Alan Weir - 1986 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27 (4):459-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Tonk.Steven Wagner - 1981 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 22 (4):289-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The co-ordination principles: A problem for bilateralism.Fernando Ferreira - 2008 - Mind 117 (468):1051-1057.
    In "'Yes" and "No'" (2000), Ian Rumfitt proposed bilateralism--a use-based account of the logical words, according to which the sense of a sentence is determined by the conditions under which it is asserted and denied. One of Rumfitt's key claims is that bilateralism can provide a justification of classical logic. This paper raises a techical problem for Rumfitt's proposal, one that seems to undermine the bilateralist programme.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Yes and no.I. Rumfitt - 2000 - Mind 109 (436):781-823.
    In what does the sense of a sentential connective consist? Like many others, I hold that its sense lies in rules that govern deductions. In the present paper, however, I argue that a classical logician should take the relevant deductions to be arguments involving affirmative or negative answers to yes-or-no questions that contain the connective. An intuitionistic logician will differ in concentrating exclusively upon affirmative answers. I conclude by arguing that a well known intuitionistic criticism of classical logic fails if (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • Harmony and autonomy in classical logic.Stephen Read - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (2):123-154.
    Michael Dummett and Dag Prawitz have argued that a constructivist theory of meaning depends on explicating the meaning of logical constants in terms of the theory of valid inference, imposing a constraint of harmony on acceptable connectives. They argue further that classical logic, in particular, classical negation, breaks these constraints, so that classical negation, if a cogent notion at all, has a meaning going beyond what can be exhibited in its inferential use. I argue that Dummett gives a mistaken elaboration (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • The Runabout Inference-Ticket.A. N. Prior - 1960 - Analysis 21 (2):38-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   291 citations  
  • The categoricity problem and truth-value gaps.I. Rumfitt - 1997 - Analysis 57 (4):223-235.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Expressive Power and Incompleteness of Propositional Logics.James W. Garson - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (2):159-171.
    Natural deduction systems were motivated by the desire to define the meaning of each connective by specifying how it is introduced and eliminated from inference. In one sense, this attempt fails, for it is well known that propositional logic rules underdetermine the classical truth tables. Natural deduction rules are too weak to enforce the intended readings of the connectives; they allow non-standard models. Two reactions to this phenomenon appear in the literature. One is to try to restore the standard readings, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The runabout inference ticket.Arthur Prior - 1967 - In P. F. Strawson (ed.), Philosophical logic. London,: Oxford University Press. pp. 38-9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  • Methoden zur Axiomatisierung beliebiger Aussagen- und Prädikatenkalküle.Karl Schröter - 1955 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 1 (4):241-251.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Co-ordination principles: A reply.Ian Rumfitt - 2008 - Mind 117 (468):1059-1063.
    I explain why Fernando Ferreira's interesting formal result does not threaten the bilateralist account of the sense of the connectives.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Generalized definitional reflection and the inversion principle.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 2007 - Logica Universalis 1 (2):355-376.
    . The term inversion principle goes back to Lorenzen who coined it in the early 1950s. It was later used by Prawitz and others to describe the symmetric relationship between introduction and elimination inferences in natural deduction, sometimes also called harmony. In dealing with the invertibility of rules of an arbitrary atomic production system, Lorenzen’s inversion principle has a much wider range than Prawitz’s adaptation to natural deduction. It is closely related to definitional reflection, which is a principle for reasoning (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Classical harmony: Rules of inference and the meaning of the logical constants.Peter Milne - 1994 - Synthese 100 (1):49 - 94.
    The thesis that, in a system of natural deduction, the meaning of a logical constant is given by some or all of its introduction and elimination rules has been developed recently in the work of Dummett, Prawitz, Tennant, and others, by the addition of harmony constraints. Introduction and elimination rules for a logical constant must be in harmony. By deploying harmony constraints, these authors have arrived at logics no stronger than intuitionist propositional logic. Classical logic, they maintain, cannot be justified (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Price and Rumfitt on rejective negation and classical logic.Peter Gibbard - 2002 - Mind 111 (442):297-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Unilateralism disarmed: A reply to Dummett and Gibbard.Ian Rumfitt - 2002 - Mind 111 (442):305-322.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Semantic Holism.Nuel D. Belnap Jr & Gerald J. Massey - 1990 - Studia Logica 49 (1):67 - 82.
    A bivalent valuation is snt iff sound (standard PC inference rules take truths only into truths) and non-trivial (not all wffs are assigned the same truth value). Such a valuation is normal iff classically correct for each connective. Carnap knew that there were non-normal snt valuations of PC, and that the gap they revealed between syntax and semantics could be "jumped" as follows. Let $VAL_{snt}$ be the set of snt valuations, and $VAL_{nrm}$ be the set of normal ones. The bottom (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Truth Values and Proof Theory.Greg Restall - 2009 - Studia Logica 92 (2):241-264.
    I present an account of truth values for classical logic, intuitionistic logic, and the modal logic S5, in which truth values are not a fundamental category from which the logic is defined, but rather, an idealisation of more fundamental logical features in the proof theory for each system. The result is not a new set of semantic structures, but a new understanding of how the existing semantic structures may be understood in terms of a more fundamental notion of logical consequence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Methoden zur Axiomatisierung Beliebiger Aussagen- und Pradikatenkalkule.J. Barkley Rosser & Karl Schroter - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation