Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)The Power of a Propositional Constant.Robert Goldblatt & Tomasz Kowalski - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (1):133-152.
    Monomodal logic has exactly two maximally normal logics, which are also the only quasi-normal logics that are Post complete, and they are complete for validity in Kripke frames. Here we show that addition of a propositional constant to monomodal logic allows the construction of continuum many maximally normal logics that are not valid in any Kripke frame, or even in any complete modal algebra. We also construct continuum many quasi-normal Post complete logics that are not normal. The set of extensions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Power of a Propositional Constant.Robert Goldblatt & Tomasz Kowalski - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Logic (1):1-20.
    Monomodal logic has exactly two maximally normal logics, which are also the only quasi-normal logics that are Post complete, and they are complete for validity in Kripke frames. Here we show that addition of a propositional constant to monomodal logic allows the construction of continuum many maximally normal logics that are not valid in any Kripke frame, or even in any complete modal algebra. We also construct continuum many quasi-normal Post complete logics that are not normal. The set of extensions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Replacement in Logic.Lloyd Humberstone - 2013 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 42 (1):49-89.
    We study a range of issues connected with the idea of replacing one formula by another in a fixed context. The replacement core of a consequence relation ⊢ is the relation holding between a set of formulas {A1,..., Am,...} and a formula B when for every context C, we have C,..., C,... ⊢ C. Section 1 looks at some differences between which inferences are lost on passing to the replacement cores of the classical and intuitionistic consequence relations. For example, we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Minimal Non-contingency Logic.Steven T. Kuhn - 1995 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 36 (2):230-234.
    Simple finite axiomatizations are given for versions of the modal logics K and K4 with non-contingency (or contingency) as the sole modal primitive. This answers two questions of I. L. Humberstone.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Some embedding theorems for modal logic.David Makinson - 1971 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 12 (2):252-254.
    Some results on the upper end of the lattice of all modal propositional logics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • A warning about the choice of primitive operators in modal logic.David Makinson - 1973 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 2 (2):193 - 196.
    Draws attention to some unexpected consequences of using a zero-ary connective in modal propositional logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Modal incompleteness revisited.Tadeusz Litak - 2004 - Studia Logica 76 (3):329 - 342.
    In this paper, we are going to analyze the phenomenon of modal incompleteness from an algebraic point of view. The usual method of showing that a given logic L is incomplete is to show that for some L and some cannot be separated from by a suitably wide class of complete algebras — usually Kripke algebras. We are going to show that classical examples of incomplete logics, e.g., Fine logic, are not complete with respect to any class of complete BAOs. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Singulary extensional connectives: A closer look. [REVIEW]I. L. Humberstone - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (3):341-356.
    The totality of extensional 1-ary connectives distinguishable in a logical framework allowing sequents with multiple or empty (alongside singleton) succedents form a lattice under a natural partial ordering relating one connective to another if all the inferential properties of the former are possessed by the latter. Here we give a complete description of that lattice; its Hasse diagram appears as Figure 1 in §2. Simple syntactic descriptions of the lattice elements are provided in §3; §§4 and 5 give some additional (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Contra-classical logics.Lloyd Humberstone - 2000 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (4):438 – 474.
    Only propositional logics are at issue here. Such a logic is contra-classical in a superficial sense if it is not a sublogic of classical logic, and in a deeper sense, if there is no way of translating its connectives, the result of which translation gives a sublogic of classical logic. After some motivating examples, we investigate the incidence of contra-classicality (in the deeper sense) in various logical frameworks. In Sections 3 and 4 we will encounter, originally as an example of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Denumerably Many Post-Complete Normal Modal Logics with Propositional Constants.Rohan French - 2012 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 53 (4):549-556.
    We show that there are denumerably many Post-complete normal modal logics in the language which includes an additional propositional constant. This contrasts with the case when there is no such constant present, for which it is well known that there are only two such logics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Continuum Many Maximal Consistent Normal Bimodal Logics with Inverses.Timothy Williamson - 1998 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 39 (1):128-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Extensionality in sentence position.Lloyd Humberstone - 1986 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 15 (1):27 - 54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Aggregation and idempotence.Lloyd Humberstone - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (4):680-708.
    A 1-ary sentential context is aggregative (according to a consequence relation) if the result of putting the conjunction of two formulas into the context is a consequence (by that relation) of the results of putting first the one formula and then the other into that context. All 1-ary contexts are aggregative according to the consequence relation of classical propositional logic (though not, for example, according to the consequence relation of intuitionistic propositional logic), and here we explore the extent of this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The inadequacy of the neighbourhood semantics for modal logic.Martin Gerson - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (2):141-148.
    We present two finitely axiomatized modal propositional logics, one betweenTandS4 and the other an extension ofS4, which are incomplete with respect to the neighbourhood or Scott-Montague semantics.Throughout this paper we are referring to logics which contain all the classical connectives and only one modal connective □ (unary), no propositional constants, all classical tautologies, and which are closed under the rules of modus ponens (MP), substitution, and the rule RE (fromA↔Binfer αA↔ □B). Such logics are calledclassicalby Segerberg [6]. Classical logics which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations