Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Why the Liberty of Indifference Is Worth Wanting: Buridan's Ass, Friendship, and Peter John Olivi.Sharon M. Kaye - 2004 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 21 (1):21 - 42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Incompatibilism, Sin, and Free Will in Heaven.Kevin Timpe & Timothy Pawl - 2009 - Faith and Philosophy 26 (4):396-417.
    The traditional view of heaven holds that the redeemed in heaven both have free will and are no longer capable of sinning. A number of philosophers have argued that the traditional view is problematic. How can someone be free and yet incapable of sinning? If the redeemed are kept from sinning, their wills must be reined in. And if their wills are reined in, it doesn’t seem right to say that they are free. Following James Sennett, we call this objection (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Anselm.Sandra Visser & Thomas Williams - 2009 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Thomas Williams.
    The reason of faith -- Thought and language -- Truth -- The Monologion arguments for the existence of God -- The Proslogion argument for the existence of God -- The divine attributes -- Thinking and speaking about God -- Creation and the word -- The Trinity -- Modality -- Freedom -- Morality -- Incarnation and atonement -- Original sin, grace, and salvation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • (1 other version)Grades of freedom: Augustine and Descartes.Christopher Gilbert - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (2):201–224.
    : While Augustine distinguishes free choice from true liberty, his account of human freedom implies further distinctions which Augustine himself does not make explicit. More importantly, Augustine regards these distinct types of freedom as qualitatively different; some are clearly superior to others. Descartes also distinguishes qualitatively different types of freedom, and does so in a way that parallels Augustine's view. I here argue that Augustine divides freedom into four qualitatively distinct grades, and then demonstrate that Descartes’ account of freedom is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Asymmetrical freedom.Susan Wolf - 1980 - Journal of Philosophy 77 (March):151-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Freedom and Resentment.Peter Strawson - 1962 - Proceedings of the British Academy 48:187-211.
    The doyen of living English philosophers, by these reflections, took hold of and changed the outlook of a good many other philosophers, if not quite enough. He did so, essentially, by assuming that talk of freedom and responsibility is talk not of facts or truths, in a certain sense, but of our attitudes. His more explicit concern was to look again at the question of whether determinism and freedom are consistent with one another -- by shifting attention to certain personal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1312 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Freedom and Resentment.Peter Strawson - 1982 - In Gary Watson (ed.), Free will. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   790 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Development and the Significance of the Concept of Responsibility.Richard Mckeon - 1957 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 11 (39):3-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Picking and Choosing: Anselm and Ockham on Choice. Normore - 1998 - Vivarium 36 (1):23-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Freedom of the Will in Plato and Augustine.Jonathan Hecht - 2014 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (2):196-216.
    There has been a recent surge of interest in ancient accounts of free will. It is surprising, then, that there have been virtually no attempts to discuss whether Plato had such an account. Those who have made an attempt quickly deny that such an account is present in the dialogues. I shall argue that if we draw a distinction between two notions of free will, it is plausible that some account of free will is, in fact, present in the dialogues, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Origin of Scotus's Theory of Synchronic Contingency.Stephen D. Dumont - 1995 - Modern Schoolman 72 (2-3):149-167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the Value of Freedom To Do Evil.Joshua Rasmussen - 2013 - Faith and Philosophy 30 (4):418-428.
    Theists typically think the freedom to choose between right and wrong is a great good . Yet, they also typically think that the very best being—God—and inhabitants of the very best place—heaven—lack this kind of freedom. The question arises: if freedom to choose evil is so good, then why is it absent from the best being and the best place? I discuss articulations of this question in the literature and point out drawbacks of answers that have been proposed. I then (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On Plato, Meno 5. By C.W.F.A. Wolf. In Lat. Progr., Halle.Christian Wilhelm Friedrich A. Wolf - 1795
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
  • Responsibility and rational abilities: Defending an asymmetrical view.Dana K. Nelkin - 2008 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 89 (4):497-515.
    Abstract: In this paper, I defend a view according to which one is responsible for one's actions to the extent that one has the ability to do the right thing for the right reasons. The view is asymmetrical in requiring the ability to do otherwise when one acts badly or for bad reasons, but no such ability in cases in which one acts well for good ones. Despite its intuitive appeal, the view's asymmetry makes it a target of both of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Salvation in Heaven.Yujin Nagasawa - 2004 - Philosophical Papers 33 (1):97-119.
    The aim of this paper is to examine the difficulties that belief in a paradisiacal afterlife creates for orthodox theists. In particular, we consider the difficulties that arise when one asks whether there is freedom in Heaven, i.e. whether the denizens of Heaven have libertarian freedom in action. Our main contention is that this 'Problem of Heaven' makes serious difficulties for proponents of free will theodicies and for proponents of free will defences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • God, Freedom, and Evil.Alvin Plantinga - 1978 - Religious Studies 14 (3):407-409.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   170 citations  
  • Peter John olivi.Robert Pasnau - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Insolente liberté: controverses et condamnations au XIIIe siècle.François-Xavier Putallaz - 1995 - Cerf.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Anselm on Freedom.Katherin A. Rogers - 2008 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Can human beings be free and responsible if there is an all-powerful God? Anselm of Canterbury offers viable answers to questions which have plagued religious people for at least two thousand years. Katherin Rogers examines Anselm's reconciliation of human free will and divine omnipotence in the context of current philosophical debates.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • What is Freedom?Jamie Anne Spiering - 2015 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 89 (1):27-46.
    Josef Pieper wrote about “the silence of St. Thomas”—faced with some of philosophy’s toughest questions, Thomas does not give “a textbook reply.” In this paper, I note an instance of such silence: Thomas gives no dogmatic, unequivocal answer to the question “What is freedom?” and this omission seems to have been deliberate. While his predecessors and contemporaries discussed the definition of freedom formally, Thomas does not do so, nor does he offer a precise account of libertas. Why would Thomas avoid (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Freedom, Contingency, and Rational Power.Calvin Normore - 2007 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 81 (2):49 - 64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Categories and logic in Duns Scotus: an interpretation of Aristotle's Categories in the late thirteenth century.Georgio Pini - 2001 - Boston: Brill.
    This study of the interpretations of Aristotle's "Categories" in the thirteenth century provides an introduction to some main themes of medieval philosophical ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Grades of Freedom: Augustine and Descartes.Christopher Gilbert - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (2):201-224.
    While Augustine distinguishes free choice from true liberty, his account of human freedom implies further distinctions which Augustine himself does not make explicit. More importantly, Augustine regards these distinct types of freedom as qualitatively different; some are clearly superior to others. Descartes also distinguishes qualitatively different types of freedom, and does so in a way that parallels Augustine's view. I here argue that Augustine divides freedom into four qualitatively distinct grades, and then demonstrate that Descartes’ account of freedom is a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Peter Olivi's Rejection of God's Concurrence with Created Causes.Gloria Frost - 2014 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (4):655-679.
    The relationship between divine and created causality was widely discussed in medieval and early modern philosophy. Contemporary scholars of these discussions typically stake out three possible positions: occasionalism, concurrentism, and mere-conservationism. It is regularly claimed that virtually no medieval thinker adopted the final view which denies that God is an immediate active cause of creaturely actions. The main aim of this paper is to further understanding of the medieval causality debate, and particularly the mere-conservationist position, by analysing Peter John Olivi's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Voluntary Action and Rational Sin in Anselm of Canterbury.Tomas Ekenberg - 2016 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (2):215-230.
    Anselm of Canterbury holds that freedom of the will is a necessary condition for moral responsibility. This condition, however, turns out to be trivially fulfilled by all rational creatures at all times. In order to clarify the necessary conditions for moral responsibility, we must look more widely at his discussion of the nature of the will and of willed action. In this paper, I examine his theory of voluntariness by clarifying his account of the sin of Satan in De casu (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The moral life.Bonnie Kent - 2003 - In Arthur Stephen McGrade (ed.), The Cambridge companion to medieval philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 231--253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Free will and Self-control in Peter Olivi.Mikko Yrjönsuuri - 2002 - In Henrik Lagerlund & Mikko Yrjönsuuri (eds.), Emotions and choice from boethius to descartes. kluwer. pp. 99--128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Freedom within Reason.Gary Watson - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):890.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  • Virtues of the Will: The Transformation of Ethics in the Late Thirteenth Century by Bonnie Kent. [REVIEW]Philip L. Quinn - 1996 - Journal of Philosophy 93 (12):628-631.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Augustine’s Notion of Freedom.Johannes Brachtendorf - 2007 - Augustinian Studies 38 (1):219-231.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations