Switch to: Citations

References in:

Interpretationism and judgement-dependence

Synthese 198 (10):9639-9659 (2020)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Truth and objectivity.Crispin Wright - 1992 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Recasting important questions about truth and objectivity in new and helpful terms, his book will become a focus in the contemporary debates over realism, and ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   726 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on rules and private language.Saul Kripke - 1982 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 173 (4):496-499.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1048 citations  
  • (2 other versions)On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme.Donald Davidson - 1973 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 47:5-20.
    Davidson attacks the intelligibility of conceptual relativism, i.e. of truth relative to a conceptual scheme. He defines the notion of a conceptual scheme as something ordering, organizing, and rendering intelligible empirical content, and calls the position that employs both notions scheme-content dualism. He argues that such dualism is untenable since: not only can we not parcel out empirical content sentence per sentence but also the notion of uninterpreted content to which several schemes are relative, and the related notion of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   608 citations  
  • (1 other version)Knowing One’s Own Mind.Donald Davidson - 1987 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 60 (3):441-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   522 citations  
  • (2 other versions)On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme.Donald Davidson - 2011 - In Robert B. Talisse & Scott F. Aikin (eds.), The Pragmatism Reader: From Peirce Through the Present. Princeton University Press. pp. 286-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   405 citations  
  • (1 other version)The rule-following considerations.Paul Boghossian - 1989 - Mind 98 (392):507-49.
    I. Recent years have witnessed a great resurgence of interest in the writings of the later Wittgenstein, especially with those passages roughly, Philosophical Investigations p)I 38 — 242 and Remarks on the Foundations of mathematics, section VI that are concerned with the topic of rules. Much of the credit for all this excitement, unparalleled since the heyday of Wittgenstein scholarship in the early IIJ6os, must go to Saul Kripke's I4rittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. It is easy to explain why. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   301 citations  
  • Truth and Objectivity.Crispin Wright - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (4):883-890.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   417 citations  
  • Oughts and thoughts: rule-following and the normativity of content.Anandi Hattiangadi - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In Oughts and Thoughts, Anandi Hattiangadi provides an innovative response to the argument for meaning skepticism set out by Saul Kripke in Wittgenstein on ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • First person authority.Donald Davidson - 1984 - Dialectica 38 (2‐3):101-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   205 citations  
  • (1 other version)Knowing One's Own Mind.Donald Davidson - 2003 - In John Heil (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   241 citations  
  • Subjective, intersubjective, objective.Donald Davidson - 1996 - In Current Issues in Idealism. Bristol: Thoemmes. pp. 555-558.
    This is the long-awaited third volume of philosophical writings by Davidson, whose influence on philosophy since the 1960s has been deep and broad. His first two collections, published by Oxford in the early 1980s, are recognized as contemporary classics. His ideas have continued to flow; now, in this new work, he presents a selection of his best work on knowledge, mind, and language from the last two decades. It is a rich and rewarding feast for anyone interested in philosophy, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   201 citations  
  • A Sceptical Guide to Meaning and Rules: Defending Kripke’s Wittgenstein.Martin Kusch - 2006 - Mcgill-Queen's University Press.
    No other recent book in Anglophone philosophy has attracted as much criticism and has found so few friends as Saul Kripke's "Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language". Amongst its critics, one finds the very top of the philosophical profession. Yet, it is rightly counted amongst the books that students of philosophy, at least in the Anglo-American world, have to read at some point in their education. Enormously influential, it has given rise to debates that strike at the very heart of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Objectivity refigured: Pragmatism without verificationism.Mark Johnston - 1993 - In John Haldane & Crispin Wright (eds.), Reality, representation, and projection. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 85--130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • Saving the differences: essays on themes from Truth and objectivity.Crispin Wright - 2003 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Edited by Crispin Wright.
    The essays in this companion volume prefigure, elaborate, or defend the proposals put forward in that landmark work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Donald Davidson’s Triangulation Argument: A Philosophical Inquiry.Robert H. Myers & Claudine Verheggen - 2015 - New York: Routledge.
    According to many commentators, Davidson’s earlier work on philosophy of action and truth-theoretic semantics is the basis for his reputation, and his later forays into broader metaphysical and epistemological issues, and eventually into what became known as the triangulation argument, are much less successful. This book by two of his former students aims to change that perception. In Part One, Verheggen begins by providing an explanation and defense of the triangulation argument, then explores its implications for questions concerning semantic normativity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Replies.Crispin Wright - 2012 - In Annalisa Coliva (ed.), Mind, meaning, and knowledge: themes from the philosophy of Crispin Wright. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 201-219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Inaugural Address: Moral Values, Projection and Secondary Qualities.Crispin Wright - 1988 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 62 (1):1 - 26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Donald Davidson: A Short Introduction.Kathrin Glüer - 2011 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    In this book, Kathrin Gl¨uer carefully outlines Donald Davidson's principal claims and arguments, and discusses them in some detail, providing a concise, systematic introduction to all the main elements of Davidson's philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Interpretivism.Alex Byrne - 1998 - European Review of Philosophy 3 (Response-Dependence):199-223.
    In the writings of Daniel Dennett and Donald Davidson we find something like the following bold conjecture: it is an a priori truth that there is no gap between our best judgements of a subject's beliefs and desires and the truth about the subject's beliefs and desires. Under ideal conditions a subject's belief-box and desire-box become transparent.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Quine on the Indeterminacy of Translation: A Dilemma for Davidson.Ali Hossein Khani - 2018 - Dialectica 72 (1):101-120.
    Davidson has always been explicit in his faithful adherence to the main doctrines of Quine’s philosophy of language, among which the indeterminacy of translation thesis is significant. For Quine, the indeterminacy of translation has considerable ontological consequences, construed as leading to a sceptical conclusion regarding the existence of fine-grained meaning facts. Davidson’s suggested reading of Quine’s indeterminacy arguments seems to be intended to block any such sceptical consequences. According to this reading, Quine’s arguments at most yield the conclusion that there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Davidson’s Answer to Kripke’s Sceptic.Olivia Sultanescu & Claudine Verheggen - 2019 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 7 (2):8-28.
    According to the sceptic Saul Kripke envisages in his celebrated book on Wittgenstein on rules and private language, there are no facts about an individual that determine what she means by any given expression. If there are no such facts, the question then is, what justifies the claim that she does use expressions meaningfully? Kripke’s answer, in a nutshell, is that she by and large uses her expressions in conformity with the linguistic standards of the community she belongs to. While (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Blind rule-following.Paul A. Boghossian - 2012 - In Annalisa Coliva (ed.), Mind, meaning, and knowledge: themes from the philosophy of Crispin Wright. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 27-48.
    In this chapter a new problem about rule-following is outlined, one that is distinct both from Kripke’s and Wright’s versions of the problem. This new problem cannot be correctly responsed to, as Kripke’s can, by invoking Wright’s Intentional Account of rule-following. The upshot might be called, following Kant, an antinomy of pure reason: we both must — and cannot — make sense of someone’s following a rule. The chapter explores various ways out of this antinomy without here endorsing any of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Kripke’s Wittgenstein’s Sceptical Paradox: A Trilemma for Davidson.Ali Hossein Khani - 2019 - International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 9 (1):21–37.
    Davidson’s later philosophy of language has been inspired by Wittgenstein’s Investigations, but Davidson by no means sympathizes with the sceptical problem and solution Kripke attributes to Wittgenstein. Davidson criticizes the sceptical argument for relying on the rule-following conception of meaning, which is, for him, a highly problematic view. He also casts doubt on the plausibility of the sceptical solution as unjustifiably bringing in shared practices of a speech community. According to Davidson, it is rather success in mutual interpretation that explains (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kripke on Wittgenstein and normativity.George M. Wilson - 1994 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1):366-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • (1 other version)Rails to Infinity: Essays on Themes from Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations.Crispin Wright - 2003 - Mind 112 (446):307-322.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • (1 other version)Rails to Infinity: Essays on Themes from Wittgenstein's 'Philosophical Investigations'.Crispin Wright - 2004 - Philosophical Quarterly 54 (214):183-186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Saving the Differences: Essays on Themes from Truth and Objectivity.Crispin Wright - 2004 - Philosophical Quarterly 54 (217):595-603.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Replies.Crispin Wright - 2000 - Philosophical Issues 10 (1):201-219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Davidson's second person.Claudine Verheggen - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (188):361-369.
    According to Donald Davidson, language is social in that only a person who has interacted linguistically with another could have a language. This paper is a discussion of Davidson’s argument in defence of that claim. I argue that he has not succeeded in establishing it, but that he has provided many of the materials out of which a successful argument could be built. Chief among these are the claims that some version of externalism about meaning is true, that possession of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Best opinion and intentional states.Jim Edwards - 1992 - Philosophical Quarterly 42 (166):21-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • How social must language be?Claudine Verheggen - 2006 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 36 (2):203-219.
    According to the communitarian view, often attributed to the later Wittgenstein, language is social in the sense that having a (first) language essentially depends on meaning by one's words what members of some community mean by them. According to the interpersonal view, defended by Davidson, language is social only in the sense that having a (first) language essentially depends on having used (at least some of) one's words, whatever one means by them, to communicate with others. Even though these views (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Donald Davidson: Looking Back, Looking Forward.Claudine Verheggen - 2019 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 7 (2):7-28.
    The papers collected in this issue were solicited to celebrate the hundredth anniversary of Donald Davidson’s birth. Four of them discuss the implications of Davidson’s views—in particular, his later views on triangulation—for questions that are still very much at the centre of current debates. These are, first, the question whether Saul Kripke’s doubts about meaning and rule-following can be answered without making concessions to the sceptic or to the quietist; second, the question whether a way can be found to answer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A modest solution to the problem of rule-following.Frank A. Hindriks - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 121 (1):65-98.
    A modest solution to the problem(s) of rule-following is defended against Kripkensteinian scepticism about meaning. Even though parts of it generalise to other concepts, the theory as a whole applies to response-dependent concepts only. It is argued that the finiteness problem is not nearly as pressing for such concepts as it may be for some other kinds of concepts. Furthermore, the modest theory uses a notion of justification as sensitivity to countervailing conditions in order to solve the justification problem. Finally, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • An Objection to Wright's Treatment of Intention.Alexander Miller - 1989 - Analysis 49 (4):169 - 173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Replies.Crispin Wright - 2000 - Noûs 34 (s1):201-219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)Another objection to Wright's treatment of intention.Alexander Miller - 2007 - Analysis 67 (3):257–263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Primary qualities, secondary qualities and the truth about intention.Alexander Miller - 2009 - Synthese 171 (3):433 - 442.
    In this paper I will argue that Crispin Wright’s defence of the claim that the truth about intention is judgement-dependent is unstable because it can serve also to establish that the truth about shape is judgement-dependent, thereby violating his constraint that in developing the distinction between judgement-independent and judgement-dependent subject matters we have to be driven by the assumption that colour and shape will fall on different sides of the divide.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Replies.Annalisa Coliva - 2013 - Philosophia 41 (1):81-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Objectivity Disfigured.Alexander Miller - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4):857-868.
    Mark Johnston has recently attacked various versions of subjectivism and anti-realism, using what he calls the “missing-explanation argument”. In this paper I shall outline the MEA, and show how Johnston takes it to demolish some anti-realist views, both historical and contemporary. In particular, I shall outline how the argument would apply to the view about the origin of piety espoused by Euthyphro in Plato’s dialogue of that name, to the judgement-dependent conception of intentional states recently sketched by Crispin Wright, to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)Expression, truth, and reality : some variations on themes from Wright.Dorit Bar-On - 2012 - In Annalisa Coliva (ed.), Mind, meaning, and knowledge: themes from the philosophy of Crispin Wright. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Expressivism, broadly construed, is the view that the function of utterances in a given area of discourse is to give expression to our sentiments or other (non-cognitive) mental states or attitudes, rather than report or describe some range of facts. This view naturally seems an attractive option wherever it is suspected that there may not be a domain of facts for the given discourse to be describing. Familiarly, to avoid commitment to ethical facts, the ethical expressivist suggests that ethical utterances (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Problems for a construction of meaning and intention.Peter M. Sullivan - 1994 - Mind 103 (410):147-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Intention detecting.Richard Holton - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (172):298-318.
    Crispin Wright has argued that our concept of intention is extension-determining, and that this explains why we are so good at knowing our intentions: it does so by subverting the idea that we detect them. This paper has two aims. The first is to make sense of Wright's claim that intention is extension-determining; this is achieved by comparing his position to that of analytic functionalism. The second is to show that it doesn't follow from this that we do not detect (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Intentions, response-dependence, and immunity from error.Richard Holton - 1991 - In P. Menzies (ed.), Response Dependent Concepts. ANU Working Papers in Philosophy 1.
    You are, I suspect, exceedingly good at knowing what you intend to do. In saying this I pay you no special compliment. Knowing what one intends is the normal state to be in. And this cries out for some explanation. How is it that we are so authoritative about our own intentions? There are two different approaches that one can take in answering this question. The first credits us with special perceptual powers which we use when we examine our own (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Best opinion, intention-detecting and analytic functionalism.John Divers & Alexander Miller - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (175):239-245.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Secondary qualities and the a priori.Jim Edwards - 1992 - Mind 101 (402):263-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Another objection to Wright's treatment of intention.Alexander Miller - 2007 - Analysis 67 (295):257-263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Donald Davidson’s Triangulation Argument: A Philosophical Inquiry. [REVIEW]Ali Hossein Khani - 2018 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 26 (1):113-117.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations