Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (4 other versions)The Road since Structure.Thomas S. Kuhn, J. Conant & J. Haugeland - 2001 - Philosophy of Science 68 (4):573-575.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • (4 other versions)The Road since Structure.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1990 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990:3-13.
    A highly condensed account of the author's present view of some philosophical problems unresolved in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. The concept of incommensurability, now considerably developed, remains at center stage, but the evolutionary metaphor, introduced in the final pages of the book, now also plays a principal role.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   192 citations  
  • The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1957 - Harvard University Press.
    The significance of the plurality of the Copernican Revolution is the main thrust of this undergraduate text In this study of the Copernican Revolution, the ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   218 citations  
  • Don't look but think: Imaginary scenarios in Wittgenstein's later philosophy.David R. Cerbone - 1994 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 37 (2):159 – 183.
    David Bloor has claimed that Wittgenstein is best read as offering the beginnings of a sociological theory of knowledge, despite Wittgenstein's reluctance to view his work this way. This leads him to dismiss Wittgenstein's many self?characterizations as mere ?prejudice?. In doing so, however, Bloor misses the import of Wittgenstein's work as a ?grammatical investigation?. The problems inherent in Bloor's interpretative approach can be discerned in his attitude toward Wittgenstein's use of imaginary scenarios: he demands that they be replaced by real (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Must We Mean What We Say?S. CAVELL - 1969
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Must we mean what we say?Stanley Cavell - 1964 - In Vere Claiborne Chappell (ed.), Ordinary language: essays in philosophical method. New York: Dover Publications. pp. 172 – 212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kuhn: philosopher of scientific revolutions.W. W. Sharrock - 2002 - Malden, MA: Polity. Edited by Rupert J. Read.
    Thomas Kuhn's shadow hangs over almost every field of intellectual inquiry. His book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions has become a modern classic. His influence on philosophy, social science, historiography, feminism, theology, and (of course) the natural sciences themselves is unparalleled. His epoch-making concepts of 'new paradigm' and 'scientific revolution' make him probably the most influential scholar of the twentieth century. Sharrock and Read take the reader through Kuhn's work in a careful and accessible way, emphasizing Kuhn's detailed studies of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The American philosopher: conversations with Quine, Davidson, Putnam, Nozick, Danto, Rorty, Cavell, MacIntyre, and Kuhn.Giovanna Borradori - 1994 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    In this lively look at current debates in American philosophy, leading philosophers talk candidly about the changing character of their discipline. In the spirit of Emerson's The American Scholar , this book explores the identity of the American philosopher. Through informal conversations, the participants discuss the rise of post-analytic philosophy in America and its relations to European thought and to the American pragmatist tradition. They comment on their own intellectual development as well as each others' work, charting the course of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The trouble with the historical philosophy of science.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1992 - Cambridge: Dept. of the History of Science, Harvard University.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Wittgenstein: a social theory of knowledge.David Bloor - 1983 - New York: Columbia University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Thomas Kuhn.Alexander Bird - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (209):654-657.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • The Road Since Structure.Kuhn Thomas (ed.) - 2000 - University of Chicago Press.
    A highly condensed account of the author's present view of some philosophical problems unresolved in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. The concept of incommensurability, now considerably developed, remains at center stage, but the evolutionary metaphor, introduced in the final pages of the book, now also plays a principal role.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Relation of History of Science to Philosophy of Science in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions and Kuhn's later philosophical work.Vasso Kindi - 2005 - Perspectives on Science 13 (4):495-530.
    In this essay I argue that Kuhn's account of science, as it was articulated in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, was mainly defended on philosophical rather than historical grounds. I thus lend support to Kuhn's later claim that his model can be derived from first principles. I propose a transcendental reading of his work and I suggest that Kuhn uses historical examples as anti-essentialist Wittgensteinian "reminders" that expose a variegated landscape in the development of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Perfect pitch and Austinian examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein, and the philosophical significance of ordinary language.Martin Gustafsson - 2005 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 48 (4):356 – 389.
    In Cavell (1994), the ability to follow and produce Austinian examples of ordinary language use is compared with the faculty of perfect pitch. Exploring this comparison, I clarify a number of central and interrelated aspects of Cavell's philosophy: (1) his way of understanding Wittgenstein's vision of language, and in particular his claim that this vision is "terrifying," (2) the import of Wittgenstein's vision for Cavell's conception of the method of ordinary language philosophy, (3) Cavell's dissatisfaction with Austin, and in particular (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Thomas Kuhn.Alexander Bird - 2000 - Routledge.
    Thomas Kuhn transformed the philosophy of science. His seminal 1962 work "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions" introduced the term 'paradigm shift' into the vernacular and remains a fundamental text in the study of the history and philosophy of science. This introduction to Kuhn's ideas covers the breadth of his philosophical work, situating "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions" within Kuhn's wider thought and drawing attention to the development of his ideas over time. Kuhn's work is assessed within the context of other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Two Cultures or One?: A Second Look at Kuhn's The Copernican Revolution.Robert S. Westman - 1994 - Isis 85 (1):79-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Two Cultures or One?: A Second Look at Kuhn's The Copernican Revolution.Robert Westman - 1994 - Isis 85:79-115.
    Thomas Kuhn's, book The Copernican Revolution deserves to be regarded as the best of that small group of longue duree histories that mark postwar historiography of science. In many respects, it is probably the single most influential one. Tightly written and brilliantly argued, it is responsible, together with The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, for the continued popularity of the metaphor of revolution in science among scholars and students alike. Yet, surprisingly, while aspects of the story conceived in Kuhn's original account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Michael N. Forster, Wittgenstein on the Arbitrariness of Grammar. [REVIEW]John Hyman - 2007 - Philosophical Review 116 (3):471-473.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Two Cultures.C. P. Snow & Stefan Collini - 2012 - Cambridge University Press.
    The notion that our society, its education system and its intellectual life, is characterised by a split between two cultures – the arts or humanities on one hand, and the sciences on the other – has a long history. But it was C. P. Snow's Rede lecture of 1959 that brought it to prominence and began a public debate that is still raging in the media today. This 50th anniversary printing of The Two Cultures and its successor piece, A Second (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Two letters of Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kühn on a draft of the structure of scientific revolutions.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 26 (3):353-387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on the Arbitrariness of Grammar.Michael N. Forster - 2004 - Princeton, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press.
    What is the nature of a conceptual scheme? Are there alternative conceptual schemes? If so, are some more justifiable or correct than others? The later Wittgenstein already addresses these fundamental philosophical questions under the general rubric of "grammar" and the question of its "arbitrariness"--and does so with great subtlety. This book explores Wittgenstein's views on these questions. Part I interprets his conception of grammar as a generalized version of Kant's transcendental idealist solution to a puzzle about necessity. It also seeks (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • From the 'will to theory 'to the discursive collage: a reply to Bloor's' Left and right Wittgensteinians'.Michael Lynch - 1992 - In Andrew Pickering (ed.), Science as practice and culture. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 283--300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Thomas Samuel Kuhn, 18 July 1922-17 June 1996.J. Heilbron - 1998 - Isis 89:505-515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Thomas Samuel Kuhn, 18 July 1922-17 June 1996.J. L. Heilbron - 1998 - Isis 89 (3):505-515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History for Our Times.Steve Fuller - 2000 - University of Chicago Press.
    This work discusses whether Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions was revolutionary. Steve Fuller argues that Kuhn held a profoundly conservative view of science and how one ought to study its history.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • On the sociology of scientific knowledge and its philosophical agenda.Michael Friedman - 1998 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 29 (2):239-271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge.David Bloor - 1984 - Human Studies 7 (3):375-386.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • 10 Kuhn, Naturalism, and the Social Study of Science.Alexander Bird - 2012 - In Vasō Kintē & Theodore Arabatzis (eds.), Kuhn's The structure of scientific revolutions revisited. New York: Routledge. pp. 205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations