Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Mechanism and fracture in cartesian physics.Mark Wilson - 1997 - Topoi 16 (2):141-152.
    I'm scarcely the only reader who has found it puzzling that the self-consistent author of the Meditations, with his firm faith that God has supplied us with clear and distinct ideas sufficient to understand the material world, could have been satisfied with the messy jumble of physical doctrine we seem to find in his ~Priuci les. For example, although Descartes seems to be committed to a relationalism of some sort, his notorious laws of impact look as if they blatantly rely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Newton on Matter and Activity.Ralph C. S. Walker & Ernan McMullin - 1980 - Philosophical Quarterly 30 (120):249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Newton’s substance monism, distant action, and the nature of Newton’s empiricism: discussion of H. Kochiras “Gravity and Newton’s substance counting problem”.Eric Schliesser - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):160-166.
    This paper is a critical response to Hylarie Kochiras’ “Gravity and Newton’s substance counting problem,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 40 267–280. First, the paper argues that Kochiras conflates substances and beings; it proceeds to show that Newton is a substance monist. The paper argues that on methodological grounds Newton has adequate resources to respond to the metaphysical problems diagnosed by Kochiras. Second, the paper argues against the claim that Newton is committed to two speculative doctrines attributed to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Breaking the circle: the emergence of Archimedean mechanics in the late Renaissance.Paolo Palmieri - 2008 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 62 (3):301-346.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Boyle's Conception of Nature.J. E. McGuire - 1972 - Journal of the History of Ideas 33 (4):523.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Newton and the mechanical philosophy: Gravitation as the balance of the heavens.Peter Machamer, J. E. Mcguire & Hylarie Kochiras - 2012 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):370-388.
    We argue that Isaac Newton really is best understood as being in the tradition of the Mechanical Philosophy and, further, that Newton saw himself as being in this tradition. But the tradition as Newton understands it is not that of Robert Boyle and many others, for whom the Mechanical Philosophy was defined by contact action and a corpuscularean theory of matter. Instead, as we argue in this paper, Newton interpreted and extended the Mechanical Philosophy's slogan “matter and motion” in reference (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A model of intelligibility in science: Using Galileo's balance as a model for understanding the motion of bodies.Peter Machamer & Andrea Woody - 1994 - Science & Education 3 (3):215-244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Gravity and Newton’s Substance Counting Problem.Hylarie Kochiras - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (3):267-280.
    A striking feature of Newton’s thought is the very broad reach of his empiricism, potentially extending even to immaterial substances, including God, minds, and should one exist, a non-perceiving immaterial medium. Yet Newton is also drawn to certain metaphysical principles—most notably the principle that matter cannot act where it is not—and this second, rationalist feature of his thought is most pronounced in his struggle to discover ‘gravity’s cause’. The causal problem remains vexing, for he neither invokes primary causation, nor accepts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Gravity and Newton’s Substance Counting Problem.Hylarie Kochiras - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (3):267-280.
    A striking feature of Newton’s thought is the very broad reach of his empiricism, potentially extending even to immaterial substances, including God, minds, and should one exist, a non-perceiving immaterial medium. Yet Newton is also drawn to certain metaphysical principles—most notably the principle that matter cannot act where it is not—and this second, rationalist feature of his thought is most pronounced in his struggle to discover ‘gravity’s cause’. The causal problem remains vexing, for he neither invokes primary causation, nor accepts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Gravity’s cause and substance counting: contextualizing the problems.Hylarie Kochiras - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):167-184.
    This paper considers Newton’s position on gravity’s cause, both conceptually and historically. With respect to the historical question, I argue that while Newton entertained various hypotheses about gravity’s cause, he never endorsed any of them, and in particular, his lack of confidence in the hypothesis of robust and unmediated distant action by matter is explained by an inclination toward certain metaphysical principles. The conceptual problem about gravity’s cause, which I identified earlier along with a deeper problem about individuating substances, is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Gravity’s cause and substance counting: contextualizing the problems.Hylarie Kochiras - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):167-184.
    This paper considers Newton’s position on gravity’s cause, both conceptually and historically. With respect to the historical question, I argue that while Newton entertained various hypotheses about gravity’s cause, he never endorsed any of them, and in particular, his lack of confidence in the hypothesis of robust and unmediated distant action by matter is explained by an inclination toward certain metaphysical principles. The conceptual problem about gravity’s cause, which I identified earlier along with a deeper problem about individuating substances, is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Locke's account of cohesion and its philosophical significance.James Hill - 2004 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 (4):611 – 630.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy.James W. Garrison - 1987 - Journal of the History of Ideas 48 (4):609-627.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Descartes, mechanics, and the mechanical philosophy.Daniel Garber - 2002 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 26 (1):185–204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Descartes. [REVIEW]Alan Gabbey - 1988 - British Journal for the History of Science 21 (1):125-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The constructible and the intelligible in Newton's philosophy of geometry.Mary Domski - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):1114-1124.
    In the preface to the Principia (1687) Newton famously states that “geometry is founded on mechanical practice.” Several commentators have taken this and similar remarks as an indication that Newton was firmly situated in the constructivist tradition of geometry that was prevalent in the seventeenth century. By drawing on a selection of Newton's unpublished texts, I hope to show the faults of such an interpretation. In these texts, Newton not only rejects the constructivism that took its birth in Descartes's Géométrie (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Mechanisms of life in the seventeenth century: Borelli, Perrault, Régis.Dennis Des Chene - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36 (2):245-260.
    In Descartes’s reformulation of natural philosophy, two aspects of what came to be known as the mechanical philosophy were intimately joined: mechanism as an ontology of nature, according to which all natural things had only ‘mechanical’ properties; and mechanism as a method of explanation. One could, and many philosophers did, adopt mechanism as a method of explanation without adopting a mechanistic ontology. I examine two successors of Descartes who did just that, and one who did not. Giovanni Alfonso Borelli in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Realism and instrumentalism in sixteenth century astronomy: A reappraisal.Peter Barker & Bernard R. Goldstein - 1998 - Perspectives on Science 6 (3):232-258.
    : We question the claim, common since Duhem, that sixteenth century astronomy, and especially the Wittenberg interpretation of Copernicus, was instrumentalistic rather than realistic. We identify a previously unrecognized Wittenberg astronomer, Edo Hildericus (Hilderich von Varel), who presents a detailed exposition of Copernicus's cosmology that is incompatible with instrumentalism. Quotations from other sixteenth century astronomers show that knowledge of the real configuration of the heavens was unattainable practically, rather than in principle. Astronomy was limited to quia demonstrations, although demonstration propter (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Isaac Barrow on the Mathematization of Nature: Theological Voluntarism and the Rise of Geometrical Optics.Antoni Malet - 1997 - Journal of the History of Ideas 58 (2):265-287.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Isaac Barrow on the Mathematization of Nature: Theological Voluntarism and the Rise of Geometrical OpticsAntoni MaletIntroductionIsaac Newton’s Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy embodies a strong program of mathematization that departs both from the mechanical philosophy of Cartesian inspiration and from Boyle’s experimental philosophy. The roots of Newton’s mathematization of nature, this paper aims to demonstrate, are to be found in Isaac Barrow’s (1630–77) philosophy of the mathematical sciences.Barrow’s attitude (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence. Edited by H. G. Alexander New York: Philosophical Library, Inc., 1956. Pp. lvi. 200. $4.75.Edward C. Moore - 1957 - Philosophy of Science 24 (4):367-369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • An Essay Concerning Human Understanding: Clarendon Edition of the Works of John Locke.Peter H. Nidditch (ed.) - 1975 - Oxford University Press UK.
    A scholarly edition of Essay Concerning Human Understanding by P. H. Nidditch. The edition presents an authoritative text, together with an introduction, commentary notes, and scholarly apparatus.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Enchiridion Metaphysicum: Sive, de Rebus Incorporeis Succincta & Luculenta Dissertatio, Per H.M. Pars Prima in Qua Quamplurima Mundi Phæomena Ad Leges Cartesii Mechanicas Obiter Expenduntur.Henry More - 1671
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Oeuvres de Descartes: mai 1647 - février 1650. Correspondance.René Descartes, Ch Adam & Paul Tannery - 1974 - J. Vrin.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   243 citations  
  • The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy.Isaac Newton - 1999 - University of California Press.
    Presents Newton's unifying idea of gravitation and explains how he converted physics from a science of explanation into a general mathematical system.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   191 citations  
  • The Mechanical Hypothesis in Ancient Greek Natural Philosophy.Sylvia Berryman - 2009 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    It has long been thought that the ancient Greeks did not take mechanics seriously as part of the workings of nature, and that therefore their natural philosophy was both primitive and marginal. In this book Sylvia Berryman challenges that assumption, arguing that the idea that the world works 'like a machine' can be found in ancient Greek thought, predating the early modern philosophy with which it is most closely associated. Her discussion ranges over topics including balancing and equilibrium, lifting water, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Newton as Philosopher.Andrew Janiak - 2008 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Newton's philosophical views are unique and uniquely difficult to categorise. In the course of a long career from the early 1670s until his death in 1727, he articulated profound responses to Cartesian natural philosophy and to the prevailing mechanical philosophy of his day. Newton as Philosopher presents Newton as an original and sophisticated contributor to natural philosophy, one who engaged with the principal ideas of his most important predecessor, René Descartes, and of his most influential critic, G. W. Leibniz. Unlike (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Mathematical principles of natural philosophy.Isaac Newton - 1726 - In Aloysius Martinich, Fritz Allhoff & Anand Vaidya (eds.), Early Modern Philosophy: Essential Readings with Commentary. Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • An Essay Concerning Human Understanding.John Locke - 1979 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 169 (2):221-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   618 citations  
  • The Mechanization of the World Picture.Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis - 1961 - Science and Society 35 (2):232-238.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence.H. G. Alexander - 1956 - Philosophy 32 (123):365-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Force and Geometry in Newton's Principia.François De Gandt - 1995
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Epistemology of the Sciences.Nicholas Jardine - 1988 - In Charles B. Schmitt, Quentin Skinner & Eckhard Kessler (eds.), The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 685--711.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Force and inertia in the seventeenth century: Descartes and Newton.Alan Gabbey - 1980 - In Stephen Gaukroger (ed.), Descartes: Philosophy, Mathematics and Physics. Barnes & Noble. pp. 230--320.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Never at Rest. A Biography of Isaac Newton.Richard S. Westfall & I. Bernard Cohen - 1982 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33 (3):305-315.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • On the notion of field in Newton, Maxwell, and beyond.Howard Stein - 1970 - In Roger H. Stuewer (ed.), Historical and Philosophical Perspectives of Science. Gordon & Breach. pp. 5--264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Newton, active powers, and the mechanical philosophy.Alan Gabbey - 2002 - In I. Bernard Cohen & George E. Smith (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Newton. Cambridge University Press. pp. 329--357.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations