Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Problems from Kant.James van Cleve - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (209):637-640.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  • (1 other version)La Science et l'Hypothèse.H. Poincaré - 1903 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 55:667-671.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  • The Emperor’s New Intuitions.Jaakko Hintikka - 1999 - Journal of Philosophy 96 (3):127-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Kant and the Exact Sciences.William Harper & Michael Friedman - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (4):587.
    This is a very important book. It has already become required reading for researchers on the relation between the exact sciences and Kant’s philosophy. The main theme is that Kant’s continuing program to find a metaphysics that could provide a foundation for the science of his day is of crucial importance to understanding the development of his philosophical thought from its earliest precritical beginnings in the thesis of 1747, right through the highwater years of the critical philosophy, to his last (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Kant on the Mathematical Method.Jaakko Hintikka - 1967 - The Monist 51 (3):352-375.
    According to Kant, “mathematical knowledge is the knowledge gained by reason from the construction of concepts.” In this paper, I shall make a few suggestions as to how this characterization of the mathematical method is to be understood.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Kant on Intuition in Geometry.Emily Carson - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (4):489 - 512.
    It's well-known that Kant believed that intuition was central to an account of mathematical knowledge. What that role is and how Kant argues for it are, however, still open to debate. There are, broadly speaking, two tendencies in interpreting Kant's account of intuition in mathematics, each emphasizing different aspects of Kant's general doctrine of intuition. On one view, most recently put forward by Michael Friedman, this central role for intuition is a direct result of the limitations of the syllogistic logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Beauty in Proofs: Kant on Aesthetics in Mathematics.Angela Breitenbach - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 23 (4):955-977.
    It is a common thought that mathematics can be not only true but also beautiful, and many of the greatest mathematicians have attached central importance to the aesthetic merit of their theorems, proofs and theories. But how, exactly, should we conceive of the character of beauty in mathematics? In this paper I suggest that Kant's philosophy provides the resources for a compelling answer to this question. Focusing on §62 of the ‘Critique of Aesthetic Judgment’, I argue against the common view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Kant on real definitions in geometry.Jeremy Heis - 2014 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44 (5-6):605-630.
    This paper gives a contextualized reading of Kant's theory of real definitions in geometry. Though Leibniz, Wolff, Lambert and Kant all believe that definitions in geometry must be ‘real’, they disagree about what a real definition is. These disagreements are made vivid by looking at two of Euclid's definitions. I argue that Kant accepted Euclid's definition of circle and rejected his definition of parallel lines because his conception of mathematics placed uniquely stringent requirements on real definitions in geometry. Leibniz, Wolff (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Kant's theory of definition.Lewis White Beck - 1956 - Philosophical Review 65 (2):179-191.
    In the modern discussions about possibility of synthetic a priori propositions, the theory of definition has a fundamental importance, because the most definition’s theories hold that analytic judgments are involved by explicit definition . However, for Kant –first author who pointed out the distinction between analytic and synthetic propositions–many analytic judgments are made by analysis of concepts which need not first be established by definition. Moreover, for him not all a priori knowledge is analytic. The statement that not all analytic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Transcendental arguments: Genuine and spurious.Jaakko Hintikka - 1972 - Noûs 6 (3):274-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Spirit of Mediaeval Philosophy.J. R. Cresswell & Etienne Gilson - 1938 - Philosophical Review 47 (3):310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Kant's gesammelte Schriften.[author unknown] - 1905 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 60:110-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Kant on the Acquisition of Geometrical Concepts.John J. Callanan - 2014 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44 (5-6):580-604.
    It is often maintained that one insight of Kant's Critical philosophy is its recognition of the need to distinguish accounts of knowledge acquisition from knowledge justification. In particular, it is claimed that Kant held that the detailing of a concept's acquisition conditions is insufficient to determine its legitimacy. I argue that this is not the case at least with regard to geometrical concepts. Considered in the light of his pre-Critical writings on the mathematical method, construction in the Critique can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Spirit of Mediaeval Philosophy.Etienne Gilson & A. H. C. Downes - 1951 - Philosophy 26 (98):275-277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Concepts and intuitions in Kant's philosophy of geometry.Joongol Kim - 2006 - Kant Studien 97 (2):138-162.
    This paper is an exposition and defense of Kant’s philosophy of geometry. The main thesis is that Euclidean geometry investigates the properties of geometrical objects in an inner space that is given to us a priori (pure space) and hence is a priori and synthetic. This thesis is supported by arguing that Euclidean geometry requires certain intuitive objects (Sect. 1), that these objects are a priori constructions in pure space (Sect. 2), and finally that the role of geometrical construction is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Der Streit über die mathematische Methode in der Philosophie in der ersten Hälfte des 18. Jahrhunderts und die Entstehung von Kants Schrift über die "Deutlichkeit".G. Tonelli - 1959 - Archiv für Philosophie 9 (1959):37.
    Cf. Jardine 1974a, p. 29; chapter 6 is 'an elegant account of developments in late scholastic debating exercises' (Jardine 1974b, 33). Cited Van den Burgh, 126 n. 95 re Grotius's method. cit. Mancosu 1996, 232 n. 39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant’s Theory of Arithmetic: A Constructive Approach?Kristina Engelhard & Peter Mittelstaedt - 2008 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 39 (2):245-271.
    Kant's theory of arithmetic is not only a central element in his theoretical philosophy but also an important contribution to the philosophy of arithmetic as such. However, modern mathematics, especially non-Euclidean geometry, has placed much pressure on Kant's theory of mathematics. But objections against his theory of geometry do not necessarily correspond to arguments against his theory of arithmetic and algebra. The goal of this article is to show that at least some important details in Kant's theory of arithmetic can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rules, examples and constructions Kant's theory of mathematics.Robert E. Butts - 1981 - Synthese 47 (2):257 - 288.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Vico'S Principle Of Verum Is Factum And The Problem Of Historicism.James C. Morrison - 1978 - Journal of the History of Ideas 39 (October-December):579-595.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Construction in Philosophy.F. W. J. Schelling - 2008 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 (2):269-288.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation