Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. How the Ceteris Paribus Laws of Physics Lie.Geert Keil - 2005 - In Jan Faye, Paul Needham, Uwe Scheffler & Max Urchs (eds.), Nature's Principles. Springer. pp. 167-200.
    After a brief survey of the literature on ceteris paribus clauses and ceteris paribus laws (1), the problem of exceptions, which creates the need for cp laws, is discussed (2). It emerges that the so-called skeptical view of laws of nature does not apply to laws of any kind whatever. Only some laws of physics are plagued with exceptions, not THE laws (3). Cp clauses promise a remedy, which has to be located among the further reactions to the skeptical view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Belief ascription: objective sentences and soft facts.Andreas Kemmerling - 2003 - Facta Philosophica 5 (2):203-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)A puzzle about belief.Saul A. Kripke - 1979 - In A. Margalit (ed.), Meaning and Use. Reidel. pp. 239--83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   557 citations  
  • "Ceteris Paribus", There Is No Problem of Provisos.John Earman & John T. Roberts - 1999 - Synthese 118 (3):439 - 478.
    Much of the literature on "ceteris paribus" laws is based on a misguided egalitarianism about the sciences. For example, it is commonly held that the special sciences are riddled with ceteris paribus laws; from this many commentators conclude that if the special sciences are not to be accorded a second class status, it must be ceteris paribus all the way down to fundamental physics. We argue that the (purported) laws of fundamental physics are not hedged by ceteris paribus clauses and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • On Kripke's puzzle.D. E. Over - 1983 - Mind 92 (366):253-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A Proposed Solution to a Puzzle about Belief.Ruth Barcan Marcus - 1981 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 6 (1):501-510.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The Import of the Puzzle About Belief.David Sosa - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (3):373-402.
    Relocating Kripke's puzzle about belief, this paper investigates i) in what the puzzle consists, exactly; ii) the method used in its construction; and iii) relations between meaning and rationality. Essential to Kripke's puzzle is a normative notion of contradictory belief. Different positions about the meaning of names yield different views of what constitutes the attribution of contradictory belief; and Kripke's puzzle unwittingly _imports a Millian assumption. Accordingly, the puzzle about belief is not independent of positions about the meaning of names.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Expressing an Intentional State.Andreas Kemmerling - unknown
    I don't have any serious quarrels with John Searle's approach to speech act theory.' There's a lot of little things that I do not really understand. (Example: what is a direction of fit?) There are a few mmor points which I think are wrong. (Example: the doctrine about "underlying rules" which are "manifested or realized" by conventions, and, to be frank, the whole thing about so called constitutive rules. Why should a statement like "Greeting in a normal context cotmts as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • .Jeremy Butterfield & John Earman - 1977
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   367 citations  
  • What's in a belief?J. I. Biro - 1984 - Logique Et Analyse 27 (7):267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Misdisquotation and substitutivity: When not to infer belief from assent.Joseph G. Moore - 1999 - Mind 108 (430):335-365.
    In 'A Puzzle about Belief' Saul Kripke appeals to a principle of disquotation that allows us to infer a person's beliefs from the sentences to which she assents (in certain conditions). Kripke relies on this principle in constructing some famous puzzle cases, which he uses to defend the Millian view that the sole semantic function of a proper name is to refer to its bearer. The examples are meant to undermine the anti-Millian objection, grounded in traditional Frege-cases, that truth-value is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Philosophical Significance of a Shared Language.Andreas Kemmerling - 1993 - In Ralf Stoecker (ed.), Reflecting Davidson: Donald Davidson responding to an international forum of philosophers. New York: W. de Gruyter. pp. 85-116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ceteris paribus laws.Stephen Schiffer - 1991 - Mind 100 (397):1-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Midwest Studies in Philosophy. French, Uehling & Wettstein (eds.) - 1981 - Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Rationality and Puzzling Beliefs.Neil Feit - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (1):29-55.
    The author presents and defends a general view about belief, and certain attributions of belief, with the intention of providing a solution to Saul Kripke's puzzle about belief. According to the position developed in the paper, there are two senses in which one could be said to have contradictory beliefs. Just one of these senses threatens the rationality of the believer; but Kripke's puzzle concerns only the other one. The general solution is then extended to certain variants of Kripke's original (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Belief and the Identity of Reference.Keith S. Donnellan - 1989 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 14 (1):275-288.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (Universität Heidelberg).Andreas Kemmerling - unknown
    since, as I said, I agree on this, I had to look pretty hard in order to find fault with any point he makes. Fortunately, his paper is a very rich one, and so I spotted two more or less incidental remarks I hoped I could reasonably disagree with. Although these two points which I shall focus on are not, as far as I can see, in any way indispensable for arriving at Manuel's main conclusion, I think they are in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Names in thought.Brian Loar - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 51 (2):169 - 185.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • What puzzling Pierre does not believe.David K. Lewis - 1981 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (3):283 – 289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations