Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)7. What Happens When Someone Acts?J. Velleman - 1993 - In John Martin Fischer & Mark Ravizza (eds.), Perspectives on moral responsibility. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. pp. 188-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • The inalienability of autonomy.Arthur Kuflik - 1984 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (4):271-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • (1 other version)A coherence theory of autonomy.Laura Waddell Ekstrom - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (3):599-616.
    This paper presents a conception of the self partially in terms of a particular notion of preference. It develops a coherentist account of when one's preferences are "authorized", or sanctioned as one's own, and presents a coherence theory of autonomous action. The view presented solves certain problems with hierarchical accounts of freedom, such as Harry Frankfurt's.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Liberalism and individual positive freedom.John Christman - 1991 - Ethics 101 (2):343-359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • (1 other version)Acting for reasons.Robert Audi - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (4):511-546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • (1 other version)Free agency.Gary Watson - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (April):205-20.
    In the subsequent pages, I want to develop a distinction between wanting and valuing which will enable the familiar view of freedom to make sense of the notion of an unfree action. The contention will be that, in the case of actions that are unfree, the agent is unable to get what he most wants, or values, and this inability is due to his own "motivational system." In this case the obstruction to the action that he most wants to do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   504 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Freedom of the will and the concept of a person.Harry G. Frankfurt - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):5-20.
    It is my view that one essential difference between persons and other creatures is to be found in the structure of a person's will. Besides wanting and choosing and being moved to do this or that, men may also want to have certain desires and motives. They are capable of wanting to be different, in their preferences and purposes, from what they are. Many animals appear to have the capacity for what I shall call "first-order desires" or "desires of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1493 citations  
  • The Significance of Emotions.Bennett W. Helm - 1994 - American Philosophical Quarterly 31 (4):319-331.
    We must distinguish between a capacity for goal-directedness of a sort found in chess-playing computers and a capacity for robust desire, which involves finding there being something in favor of the relevant course of action in light of its significance to the subject. Existing accounts of desire, especially those given in terms of instrumental rationality, either ignore or presuppose such significance, in both cases failing to give an adequate account of robust desire. My positive thesis in this paper is that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Servility and self-respect.Thomas E. Hill - 1973 - The Monist 57 (1):87 - 104.
    Thomas E. Hill, Jr.; Servility and Self-Respect, The Monist, Volume 57, Issue 1, 1 January 1973, Pages 87–104, https://doi.org/10.5840/monist197357135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Alienation, consequentialism, and the demands of morality.Peter Railton - 1984 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (2):134-171.
    The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   409 citations  
  • 14. Responsibility for Consequences.John Martin Fischer & Mark Ravizza - 1993 - In John Martin Fischer & Mark Ravizza (eds.), Perspectives on moral responsibility. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. pp. 322-348.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • The Faintest Passion.Harry Frankfurt - 1992 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 66 (3):5-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Ethical Issues in Modern Medicine.Bonnie Steinbock, John D. Arras & Alex John London - 2003 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 6 (4):447-448.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Autonomy and Personal History.John Christman - 1991 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (1):1 - 24.
    Virtually any appraisal of a person’s welfare, integrity, or moral status, as well as the moral and political theories built on such appraisals, will rely crucially on the presumption that her preferences and values are in some important sense her own. In particular, the nature and value of political freedom is intimately connected with the presupposition that actions one is left free to do flow from desires and values that are truly an expression of the ‘self-government’ of the agent. However, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • Duty and love.Harry G. Frankfurt - 1998 - Philosophical Explorations 1 (1):4 – 9.
    The grip and forcefulness of the demands that love imposes upon us resemble the forcefulness and grip of moral obligation. In cases of both kinds, we feel that we are not free to do as we please. It is a mistake, however, to presume that the requirements of love and duty are of the same kind or have the same source.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Socialization and Autonomous Behavior.Irving Thalberg - 1979 - Tulane Studies in Philosophy 28:21-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Public Conception of Autonomy and Critical Self-reflection.Robert Noggle - 1997 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 35 (4):495-515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Two Types of Autonomy Accounts.Richard Double - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1):65 - 80.
    Philosophers’ intuitions about what constitutes autonomy are largely driven by the exemplars or paradigms that we recognize. There are indefinitely many exemplars, inasmuch as there are relatively private personae that serve as autonomy exemplars such as our parents, third grade teacher, or, for the megalomaniac, oneself. But among Western philosophers there are doubtless some exemplars that are widely shared and broadly influential. Philosophical exemplars include Socrates, Aristotle’s magnanimous man, Kant’s noumenal self that is perfectly attuned to the moral law, Mill’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Defending Historical Autonomy: A Reply to Professor Mele.John Christman - 1993 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23 (2):281 - 289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations