Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A dynamic model for “science and religion”: Interacting subcultures.Richard Olson - 2011 - Zygon 46 (1):65-83.
    Abstract: I argue that for psychological and social reasons, the traditional “Conflict Model” of science and religion interactions has such a strong hold on the nonexpert imagination that counterexamples and claims that interactions are simply more complex than the model allows are inadequate to undermine its power. Taxonomies, such as those of Ian Barbour and John Haught, which characterize conflict as only one among several possible relationships, help. But these taxonomies, by themselves, fail to offer an account of why different (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Concepts and Cognitive Science.Stephen Laurence & Eric Margolis - 1999 - In Eric Margolis & Stephen Laurence (eds.), Concepts: Core Readings. MIT Press. pp. 3-81.
    Given the fundamental role that concepts play in theories of cognition, philosophers and cognitive scientists have a common interest in concepts. Nonetheless, there is a great deal of controversy regarding what kinds of things concepts are, how they are structured, and how they are acquired. This chapter offers a detailed high-level overview and critical evaluation of the main theories of concepts and their motivations. Taking into account the various challenges that each theory faces, the chapter also presents a novel approach (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   253 citations  
  • On Typologies for Relating Science and Religion.Ian G. Barbour - 2002 - Zygon 37 (2):345-360.
    Geoffrey Cantor and Chris Kenny have criticized attempts to classify various ways of relating science and religion. They hold that all typologies are too simple and too static to illuminate the complex and changing historical interactions of science and religion. I argue that typologies serve a useful pedagogical function even though every particular interaction must be seen in its historical context. I acknowledge the problems in making distinctions between categories of classification and examine some alternative typologies that have been proposed. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The continuing interaction of science and religion.John Polkinghorne - 2005 - Zygon 40 (1):43-49.
    . Stephen I Gould's notion of non‐overlapping magisteria is neither experientially supported nor rationally justifiable. Influence flows between science and religion, as when evolutionary thinking encouraged theology to adopt a kenotic view of the Creator's act of allowing creatures to be and to make themselves. Alleged simplistic dichotomies between science and religion, such as motivated belief contrasted with fideistic assertion, are seen to be false. Promising topics in the currently vigorous dialogue between science and religion include relational ontology, eschatological credibility, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Barbour's Fourfold Way: Problems with His Taxonomy of Science‐religion Relationships.Geoffrey Cantor & Chris Kenny - 2001 - Zygon 36 (4):765-781.
    In this paper several problems are raised concerning Ian Barbour's four ways of interrelating science and religion—Conflict, Independence, Dialogue, and Integration—as put forward in such publications as his highly influential Religion in an Age of Science (1990) and widely adopted by other writers in this field. The authors argue that this taxonomy is not very useful or analytically helpful, especially to historians seeking to understand past engagements between science and religion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Relevance of Tillich for the Theology and Science Dialogue.Robert John Russell - 2001 - Zygon 36 (2):269-308.
    This paper explores the relevance of the theology of Paul Tillich for the contemporary dialogue with the natural sciences. The focus is on his Systematic Theology, volume I. First I discuss the general relevance of Tillich's methodology (namely, the method of correlation) for that dialogue, stressing that a genuine dialogue requires cognitive input from both sides and that both sides find “value added” according to their own criteria (or what I call the method of “mutual creative interaction”). Then I move (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Nonoverlapping magisteria.Stephen Jay Gould - 1997 - Natural History 106 (2):16--22.
    ncongruous places often inspire anomalous stories. In early 1984, I spent several nights at the Vatican housed in a hotel built for itinerant priests. While pondering over such puzzling issues as the intended function of the bidets in each bathroom, and hungering for something other than plum jam on my breakfast rolls (why did the basket only contain hundreds of identical plum packets and not a one of, say, strawberry?), I encountered yet another among the innumerable issues of contrasting cultures (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Taking science seriously without scientism: A response to Taede Smedes.Ian G. Barbour - 2008 - Zygon 43 (1):259-269.
    . In responding to Taede Smedes, I first examine his thesis that the recent dialogue between science and religion has been dominated by scientism and does not take theology seriously. I then consider his views on divine action, free will and determinism, and process philosophy. Finally I use the fourfold typology of Conflict, Independence, Dialogue, and Integration to discuss his proposal for the future of science and religion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Faith, belief and perspective: Peter Winch's philosophy of religion.Eric O. Springsted - 2004 - Philosophical Investigations 27 (4):345–369.
    Peter Winch's philosophy of religion is controversial, accused of mere “perspectivism” and fideism, and for avoiding discussion of any existential reference for the object of belief. This essay examines what Winch meant by a “perspective.” It first deals with problems of first person propositions of belief. For Wittgenstein and Winch belief and the fact it believes are inextricably bound together. Thus Winch argues that what is said cannot be divorced from the situation of the sayer; understanding requires making shifts in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Without Answers. [REVIEW]P. T. Geach - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (17):530-532.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Philosophical investigations.Ludwig Wittgenstein & G. E. M. Anscombe - 1953 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 161:124-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3046 citations  
  • The Time That Remains: A Commentary on the Letter to the Romans.[author unknown] - 2009 - Political Theory 37 (4):562-570.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Religion, Science and Naturalism.Willem B. Drees - 1997 - American Journal of Theology and Philosophy 18 (3):297-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Conflict and Compatibility: Some Thoughts on the Relationship between Science and Religion.Ian A. McFarland - 2003 - Modern Theology 19 (2):181-202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ‘Superstition’ as a contemplative term: a Wittgensteinian perspective.Hermen Kroesbergen - 2015 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 77 (2):105-122.
    Can a contemplative philosopher describe a particular religious practice as superstitious, or is he thereby overstepping his boundaries? I will discuss the way in which the Wittgensteinian philosopher of religion D. Z. Phillips uses ‘Superstition’ as a contemplative term. His use of the distinction between genuine religion and superstition is not a weakness as is often supposed, but a necessity. Without contemplating ‘Superstition’ and ‘genuine religion’ Phillips would not have been able to elucidate the meaning that religious beliefs have in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation