Switch to: Citations

References in:

The Nature of Desire

New York, USA: Oxford University Press (2017)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A Natural History of Negation.Laurence R. Horn - 1989 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 24 (2):164-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   337 citations  
  • Vom Ursprung sittlicher erkenntniss.Franz Brentano - 1890 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 30:428-432.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Expressivism and Dispositional Desires.Caj Strandberg - 2012 - American Philosophical Quarterly 49 (1):81-91.
    According to a persistent objection against metaethical expressivism, this view is committed to a strong version of internalism which is unable to account for cases where a person’s moral judgment and motivation come apart. Recently, leading expressivists have argued that they can meet this objection by maintaining that moral judgments consist in non-cognitive states that motivate in normal conditions. In this paper, it is maintained that an important dimension of internalism has, on the whole, gone unnoticed: Internalist claims vary depending (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Intentionality.J. Searle - 1983 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 49 (3):530-531.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   598 citations  
  • Counterfactuals.David Lewis - 1973 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 36 (3):602-605.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1300 citations  
  • Instrumentalism.Christoph Fehige - 2001 - In Elijah Millgram (ed.), Varieties of Practical Reasoning. MIT Press. pp. 49--76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Methods of Ethics.Henry Sidgwick - 1890 - International Journal of Ethics 1 (1):120-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   326 citations  
  • Sympathy for the devil.Kieran Setiya - 2010 - In Sergio Tenenbaum (ed.), Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good. Oxford University Press. pp. 82--110.
    Argues that, while human beings may act "under the guise of the good," this is not true of rational agents, as such. Themes discussed along the way – extending the argument of "Reasons without Rationalism" (Princeton, 2007) – include: desires as appearances of the good, the intelligibility of vice, and the kind of essentialist claim that permits exceptions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Knowing what I want.Alex Byrne - 2011 - In JeeLoo Liu & John Perry (eds.), Consciousness and the Self: New Essays. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
    How do you know what you want? The question is neglected by epistemologists. This paper attempts an answer.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Some varieties of metaphysical dependence.E. J. Lowe - 2013 - In Miguel Hoeltje, Benjamin Schnieder & Alex Steinberg (eds.), Varieties of Dependence: Ontological Dependence, Grounding, Supervenience, Response-Dependence. Philosophia. pp. 193-210.
    In this paper, I first of all define various kinds of ontological dependence, motivating these definitions by appeal to examples. My contention is that whenever we need, in metaphysics, to appeal to some notion of existential or identity-dependence, one or other of these definitions will serve our needs adequately, which one depending on the case in hand. Then I respond to some objections to one of these proposed definitions in particular, namely, my definition of (what I call) essential identity-dependence. Finally, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On the guise of the good.Joseph Raz - 2010
    I will provisionally take the Guise of the Good thesis to consist of three propositions: (1) Intentional actions are actions performed for reasons, as those are seen by the agents. (2) Specifying the intention which makes an action intentional identifies central features of the reason(s) for which the action is performed. (3) Reasons for action are such reasons by being facts which establish that the action has some value. From these it is said to follow that (4) Intentional actions are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Experiences of value.Graham Oddie - 2009 - In Charles R. Pigden (ed.), Hume on Motivation and Virtue. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Impartial Reason.Stephen L. Darwall - 1983 - Ethics 96 (3):604-619.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   238 citations  
  • Moral vision. An introduction to Ethics.David Mcnaughton & Agnès Heller - 1990 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 180 (2):467-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • Counterfactuals.David Lewis - 1973 - Foundations of Language 13 (1):145-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1264 citations  
  • Causality and Determination.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1993 - In E. Sosa M. Tooley (ed.), Causation. Oxford Up. pp. 88-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • Ontological Dependence: An Opinionated Survey.Kathrin Koslicki - 2013 - In Benjamin Schnieder, Miguel Hoeltje & Alex Steinberg (eds.), Varieties of Dependence: Ontological Dependence, Grounding, Supervenience, Response-Dependence (Basic Philosophical Concepts). Philosophia Verlag. pp. 31-64.
    This essay provides an opinionated survey of some recent developments in the literature on ontological dependence. Some of the most popular definitions of ontological dependence are formulated in modal terms; others in non-modal terms (e.g., in terms of the explanatory connective, ‘because’, or in terms of a non-modal conception of essence); some (viz., the existential construals of ontological dependence) emphasise requirements that must be met in order for an entity to exist; others (viz., the essentialist construals) focus on conditions that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • The A Priori Foundations of the Civil Law.Adolf Reinach - 1983 - Aletheia 3:1-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Ryle on Motives and Dispositions.Maria Alvarez - 2015 - In D. Dolby (ed.), Ryle on Mind and Language. Palgrave. pp. 74-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Unconscious Belief and Conscious Thought.Tim Crane - 2013 - In Uriah Kriegel (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality. Oxford, UK: Oup Usa. pp. 156.
    We call our thoughts conscious, and we also say the same of our bodily sensations, perceptions and other sensory experiences. But thoughts and sensory experiences are very different phenomena, both from the point of view of their subject and in their functional or cognitive role. Does this mean, then, that there are very different kinds or varieties of consciousness? Philosophers do often talk about different kinds of consciousness: Christopher Hill, for example, claims that ‘it is customary to distinguish five forms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Varieties of priveleged access.William P. Alston - 1971 - American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (3):223-41.
    This paper distinguishes and interrelates a number of respects in which persons have been thought to be in a specially favorable epistemic position vis-A-Vis their own mental states. The most important distinction is a six-Fold one between infallibility, Omniscience, Indubitability, Incorrigibility, Truth-Sufficiency, And self-Warrant. Each of these varieties can then be sub-Divided as the kind of modality, If any, Involved. It is also argued that discussions of self-Knowledge have been hampered by a failure to recognize these distinctions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Are reasons causes?Severin Schroeder - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The First Person Perspective and Other Essays.Sydney Shoemaker - 1996 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 59 (2):378-378.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   196 citations  
  • On the aim of belief.J. David Velleman - manuscript
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Practical Reality.Jonathan Dancy - 2000 - Philosophy 78 (305):414-425.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   450 citations  
  • Truthlikeness.G. Oddie - 2008 - In Martin P. Curd (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science. pp. 478--488.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Concepts of Consciousness.Ned Block - 2002 - In David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press. pp. 206-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • The Concept of Welfare.R. B. Brandt - 1966 - In S. R. Krupp (ed.), The Structure of Economic Science: Essays on Methodology. pp. 257-76.
    One area in which the moral philosopher might say something useful for the thinking of economists is that of welfare economics – not by improving formalizations or criticizing proofs as to conditions necessary or sufficient for an optimum situation, much less by suggesting what particular state of society would be optimal. Rather, he can do this by pointing out some distinctions, by suggesting how some terms used by economists can profitably be defined, and by questioning some assumptions which seem to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Intention,--Plans,--and--Practical--Reason.Michael E. Bratman - 1988 - Mind 97 (388):632-634.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Dispositions.Shungho Choi & Michael Fara - 2012 - The Standford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    This is a perfect overview article that serves as a general introduction to the topic of dispositions. It is composed of six sections that review the main philosophical approaches to the most important questions: Analysis of disposition ascription, the dispositional/categorical distinction, dispositions and categorical bases, the intrinsicness of dispositions and the causal efficacy of dispositions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  • Morality and Action.Warren Quinn - 1993 - Philosophy 69 (270):513-515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • The Rationality of Emotion.Ronald DE SOUSA - 1987 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 22 (4):302-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   314 citations  
  • The Rationality of Emotion.Ronald de Sousa, Jing-Song Ma & Vincent Shen - 1987 - Philosophy and Culture 32 (10):35-66.
    How should we understand the emotional rationality? This first part will explore two models of cognition and analogy strategies, test their intuition about the emotional desire. I distinguish between subjective and objective desire, then presents with a feeling from the "paradigm of drama" export semantics, here our emotional repertoire is acquired all the learned, and our emotions in the form of an object is fixed. It is pretty well in line with the general principles of rationality, especially the lowest reasonable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   221 citations  
  • The Nature of Existence.John Mctaggart, Ellis Mctaggart & C. D. Broad - 1928 - Mind 37 (146):221-233.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Pain and Emotion.Roger Trigg - 1970 - Philosophy 46 (176):173-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought.Peter Gärdenfors - 2000 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 64 (1):180-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   328 citations  
  • Blindspots.Roy Sorensen - 1990 - Mind 99 (393):137-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   223 citations  
  • Reference and Generality: An Examination of Some Medieval and Modern Theories.Peter Thomas Geach - 1964 - Mind 73 (292):575-583.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Body and Mind: a History and a Defence of Animism.William Mcdougall - 1912 - Mind 21 (81):104-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The Character of Mind.Colin Mcginn - 1983 - Philosophy 58 (226):549-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • The Character of Mind.Colin Mcginn - 1985 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 47 (1):139-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Powers: A Study in Metaphysics.George Molnar & Stephen Mumford - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (2):485-487.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   156 citations  
  • Meinong's Theory of Objects and Values.J. N. Findlay - 1967 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 21 (4):628-629.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Meinong's theory of objects and values.J. N. Findlay - 1971 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 161:497-497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Ethics.A. C. Ewing - 1956 - Philosophy 31 (117):163-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Normativity of Evaluative Concepts.Christine Tappolet - 2014 - In Anne Reboul (ed.), Mind, Values, and Metaphysics. Philosophical Essays in Honor of Kevin Mulligan, Volume 2. pp. 39-54.
    It is generally accepted that there are two kinds of normative concepts : evaluative concepts, such as good, and deontic concepts, such as ought. The question that is raised by this distinction is how it is possible to claim that evaluative concepts are normative. Given that deontic concepts appear to be at the heart of normativity, the bigger the gap between evaluative and deontic concepts, the less it appears plausible to say that evaluative concepts are normative. After having presented the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Teleology and the nature of mental states.Scott R. Sehon - 1994 - American Philosophical Quarterly 31 (1):63-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Von der Klassification der psychischen Phenomene.Franz Brentano - 1913 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 21 (5):25-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Philosophy and the science of subjective well-being.Dan Haybron - unknown
    The Renaissance of Prudential Psychology Philosophical reflection on the good life in coming decades will likely owe a tremendous debt to the burgeoning science of subjective well-being and the pioneers, like Ed Diener, who brought it to fruition. While the psychological dimensions of human welfare now occupy a prominent position in the social sciences, they have gotten surprisingly little attention in the recent philosophical literature. The situation appears to be changing, however, as philosophers inspired by the empirical research begin to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations