Switch to: Citations

References in:

Common Sense and Ordinary Language: Wittgenstein and Austin

In Rik Peels & René van Woudenberg (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Common-Sense Philosophy. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press (2020)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Austin on Perception, Knowledge and Meaning.Krista Lawlor - 2017 - In Savas L. Tsohatzidis (ed.), Interpreting J. L. Austin: Critical Essays. Cambridge University Press.
    Austin’s Sense and Sensibilia (1962) generates wildly different reactions among philosophers. Interpreting Austin on perception starts with a reading of this text, and this in turn requires reading into the lectures key ideas from Austin’s work on natural language and the theory of knowledge. The lectures paint a methodological agenda, and a sketch of some first-order philosophy, done the way Austin thinks it should be done. Crucially, Austin calls for philosophers to bring a deeper understanding of natural language meaning to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Austin on Perception, Knowledge and Meaning.Lawlor Krista - 2017 - In Savas L. Tsohatzidis (ed.), Interpreting J. L. Austin: Critical Essays. Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Proof of an external world.George Edward Moore - 1939 - Proceedings of the British Academy 25 (5):273--300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   224 citations  
  • Warrant for nothing (and foundations for free)?Crispin Wright - 2004 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 78 (1):167–212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   497 citations  
  • What's wrong with Moore's argument?James Pryor - 2004 - Philosophical Issues 14 (1):349–378.
    Something about this argument sounds funny. As we’ll see, though, it takes some care to identify exactly what Moore has done wrong. Iwill assume that Moore knows premise (2) to be true. One could inquire into how he knows it, and whether that knowledge can be defeated; but Iwon’t. I’ll focus instead on what epistemic relations Moore has to premise (1) and to his conclusion (3). It may matter which epistemic relations we choose to consider. Some philosophers will diagnose Moore’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   344 citations  
  • Studies in the Way of Words.D. E. Over - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (160):393-395.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   431 citations  
  • Austin on Language.Brian Garvey (ed.) - 2014 - Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Looking at the work of J.L. Austin, who subjected language to a close and intense analysis, this book deals with his examination of the various things we do with words, and with the philosophical insights he believed could be gained by closely examining the uses of words by non-philosophers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Facts and Certainty.Crispin Wright - 2004 - In T. J. Smiley & Thomas Baldwin (eds.), Studies in the philosophy of logic and knowledge. New York: Published for the British Academy by Oxford University Press. pp. 429-472.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • Moore as an ordinary-language philosopher: A centenary tribute.Ralph S. Pomeroy - 1974 - Metaphilosophy 5 (2):76–105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A defence of common sense.George Edward Moore - 1925 - In J. H. Muirhead (ed.), Contemporary British Philosophy, Second Series. George Allen and Unwin.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • To what must an epistemology be true?Mark Kaplan - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (2):279-304.
    J. L. Austin famously thought that facts about the circumstances in which it is ordinarily appropriate and reasonable to make claims to knowledge have a great bearing on the propriety of a philosophical account of knowledge. His major criticism of the epistemological doctrines about which he wrote was precisely that they lacked fidelity to our ordinary linguistic practices. In The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism, Barry Stroud argues that Austin was misguided: it is one thing for it to be inappropriate under (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Reid and Wittgenstein on philosophy and language.Henning Jensen - 1979 - Philosophical Studies 36 (4):359 - 376.
    Following a detailed study of the views of reid and wittgenstein on philosophy and language, I conclude that reid's position represents an extremely pivotal stage in the upgrading of the importance of language in philosophy which, Taken up and carried along by moore, Culminates in the later philosophy of wittgenstein and that the latter owes much to views on philosophy and language which have their origin in reid.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • When Words Are Called For: A Defense of Ordinary Language Philosophy.Avner Baz - 2012 - Harvard University Press.
    The basic conflict: an initial characterization -- The main arguments against ordinary language philosophy -- Must philosophers rely on intuitions? -- Contextualism and the burden of knowledge -- Contextualism, anti-contextualism, and knowing as being in a position to give assurance -- Conclusion: skepticism and the dialectic of (semantically pure) "knowledge" -- Epilogue: ordinary language philosophy, Kant, and the roots of antinomial thinking.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Common Sense: Moore and Wittgenstein.Alan R. White - 1986 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 40 (158):313.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Scepticism, certainty, Moore and Wittgenstein.Crispin Wright - 2004 - In Max Kölbel & Bernhard Weiss (eds.), Wittgenstein's Lasting Significance. New York: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Wittgenstein.R. Fogelin - 1982 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 44 (3):561-562.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Wittgenstein's refutation of idealism.Michael Williams - 2003 - In Denis McManus (ed.), Wittgenstein and Scepticism. New York: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • To What Must an Epistemology Be True?Mark Kaplan - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (2):279-304.
    J. L. Austin famously thought that facts about the circumstances in which it is ordinarily appropriate and reasonable to make (challenge) claims to knowledge have a great bearing on the propriety of a philosophical account of knowledge. His major criticism of the epistemological doctrines about which he wrote was precisely that they lacked fidelity to our ordinary linguistic practices. In The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism, Barry Stroud argues that Austin was misguided: it is one thing for it to be inappropriate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Austin, Dreams, and Skepticism.Adam Leite - unknown
    J. L. Austin’s attitude towards traditional epistemological problems was largely negative. They arise and are maintained, he charged, by “sleight of hand,” “wile,” “concealed motives,” “seductive fallacies,” fixation on a handful of “jejune examples” and a host of small errors, misinterpretations, and mistakes about matters of fact (1962: 3- 6, 1979: 87). As these charges indicate, he did not offer a general critical theory of traditional epistemological theorizing or of the intellectual motivations that lead to it. Instead, he subjected individual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations