Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. ‘This inscrutable principle of an original organization’: epigenesis and ‘looseness of fit’ in Kant’s philosophy of science.John H. Zammito - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (1):73-109.
    Kant’s philosophy of science takes on sharp contour in terms of his interaction with the practicing life scientists of his day, particularly Johann Blumenbach and the latter’s student, Christoph Girtanner, who in 1796 attempted to synthesize the ideas of Kant and Blumenbach. Indeed, Kant’s engagement with the life sciences played a far more substantial role in his transcendental philosophy than has been recognized hitherto. The theory of epigenesis, especially in light of Kant’s famous analogy in the first Critique, posed crucial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • The Significance of §§76 and 77 Of the Critique of Judgment for the Development of Post-Kantian Philosophy (Part 2).Eckhart Förster, Karen Ng & Matthew Congdon - 2010 - Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 31 (2):323-347.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Significance of §§76 and 77 Of the Critique of Judgment for the Development of Post-Kantian Philosophy (Part 1).Eckart Förster - 2009 - Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 30 (2):197-217.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant on Understanding Organisms as Natural Purposes.Hannah Ginsborg - 2001 - In Eric Watkins (ed.), Kant and the Sciences. New York, US: Oxford University Press.
    This paper explains why Kant thinks that organisms must be regarded as purposes, and how this can be done while respecting their status as natural products rather than artifacts. Kant’s premise that organisms are mechanically inexplicable is interpreted as the claim that biological regularities are irreducible to regularities in the behavior of matter as such. His conclusion that they are purposive is interpreted as the claim that they must be regarded in normative terms. This conclusion is defended on the grounds (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • (2 other versions)3. Von der ästhetischen und logischen Vorstellung der Zweckmäßigkeit der Natur.Reinhard Brandt - 2008 - In 3. Von der ästhetischen und logischen Vorstellung der Zweckmäßigkeit der Natur. pp. 41-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Zwischen Lachen Und Weinen, Band 2, Zwischen Lachen Und Weinen: Band Ii: Der Dritte Weg Philosophischer Anthropologie Und Die Geschlechterfrage.Hans-Peter Krüger - 2001 - Akademie Verlag.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Transcendental Elements in the Philosophy of Helmuth Plessner.Rafał Michalski - 2013 - Dialogue and Universalism 23 (2):7-24.
    The essay reviews references to Immanuel Kant’s transcendental philosophy in the work of Helmuth Plessner. First discussed is the Krisis der transzendentalen Wahrheit im Anfang, in which Plessner effects a critique of the transcendental method and shows that overcoming its crisis requires philosophy to rigorously restrict the applicability of theory to the experimental sphere and put it up for judgment by the tribunal of practical reason. Next under scrutiny is Plessner’s programmatic text in philosophical anthropology, in which he strives to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The 25 Years of Philosophy: A Systematic Reconstruction.Eckart Förster - 2012 - Harvard University Press.
    Kant declared that philosophy began in 1781 with his Critique of Pure Reason. In 1806 Hegel announced that it had been completed. Förster assesses the steps that led from Kant’s “beginning” to Hegel’s “end” and concludes that both Kant and Hegel were indeed right. His study reveals Goethe’s significant contribution to post-Kantian thinking.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • (5 other versions)Critique of judgement.Immanuel Kant - 1952 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Nicholas Walker.
    In the Critique of Judgement, Kant offers a penetrating analysis of our experience of the beautiful and the sublime. He discusses the objectivity of taste, aesthetic disinterestedness, the relation of art and nature, the role of imagination, genius and originality, the limits of representation, and the connection between morality and the aesthetic. He also investigates the validity of our judgements concerning the degree in which nature has a purpose, with respect to the highest interests of reason and enlightenment. The work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  • The philosophy of the present.George Herbert Mead - 1932 - Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books. Edited by Arthur Edward Murphy.
    George Herbert Mead (1863-1931) had a powerful influence on the development of American pragmatism in the twentieth century. He also had a strong impact on the social sciences. This classic book represents Mead's philosophy of experience, so central to his outlook. The present as unique experience is the focus of this deep analysis of the basic structure of temporality and consciousness. Mead emphasizes the novel character of both the present and the past. Though science is predicated on the assumption that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • Kant's critique of teleology in biological explanation: antinomy and teleology.Peter McLaughlin - 1990 - Lewiston: E. Mellen Press.
    Kant's Critique of Teleological Judgment is read as a reflection on philosophical methodological problems that arose through the constitution of an independent science of life - biology. This work presents an example of the interconnections between philosophy and the history of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • (1 other version)The unreality of time.John Ellis McTaggart - 1908 - Mind 17 (68):457-474.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   458 citations  
  • Sein und Zeit.Martin Heidegger - 1981 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 14 (1):57-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   412 citations  
  • Kant's final synthesis: an essay on the Opus postumum.Eckart Förster - 2000 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    This is the first book in English devoted entirely to Kant's Opus postumum and its place in the Kantian oeuvre.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Gesamtausgabe Abt. 1 Veröffentlichte Schriften Bd. 2. Sein und Zeit.: Mit den Randbemerkungen aus dem Handexemplar des Autors im Anhang.Martin Heidegger (ed.) - 1977 - Halle a.: Walter de Gruyter.
    »Selten hat in den neueren Jahrhunderten ein philosophischer Erstling so durchgeschlagen und einen so unverrückbaren Platz unter den >großenHans Georg Gadamer in DIE ZEIT Nr. 47 vom 19.11.1982.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   603 citations  
  • (1 other version)Mechanical explanation of nature and its limits in Kant's Critique of judgment.Angela Breitenbach - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):694-711.
    In this paper I discuss two questions. What does Kant understand by mechanical explanation in the Critique of judgment? And why does he think that mechanical explanation is the only type of the explanation of nature available to us? According to the interpretation proposed, mechanical explanations in the Critique of judgment refer to a particular species of empirical causal laws. Mechanical laws aim to explain nature by reference to the causal interaction between the forces of the parts of matter and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • (1 other version)Teleology then and now: The question of Kant's relevance for contemporary controversies over function in biology.John Zammito - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):748-770.
    Kant -- drawing on his eighteenth-century predecessors -- provided a discerning and powerful characterization of what biologists had to explain in organic form. His difference from the rest is that he opined that was impossible to explain it. Its ’inscrutability’ was intrinsic. The third ’Critique’ essentially proposed the reduction of biology to a kind of prescientific descriptivism, doomed never to attain authentic scientificity. By contrast, for Locke, and ’a fortiori’ for Buffon and his followers, ’intrinsic purposiveness’ was a fact of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant on biological teleology: Towards a two-level interpretation.Marcel Quarfood - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):735-747.
    Kant stresses the regulative status of teleological attributions, but sometimes he seems to treat teleology as a constitutive condition for biology. To clarify this issue, the concept of natural purpose and its role for biology are examined. I suggest that the concept serves an identificatory function: it singles out objects as natural purposes, whereby the special science of biology is constituted. This relative constitutivity of teleology is explicated by means of a distinction of levels: on the object level of biological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant on understanding organisms as natural purposes.Hannah Ginsborg - 2001 - In Eric Watkins (ed.), Kant and the Sciences. New York, US: Oxford University Press. pp. 231--58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • (1 other version)Persons and Their Bodies: The Körper/Leib Distinction and Helmuth Plessner’s Theories of Ex-centric Positionality and Homo absconditus.Hans-Peter Krüger - 2010 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 24 (3):256-274.
    In German discussions over the last twenty years of the difference between what it is to be a body (in German: Leibsein) and what it is to have a body (Körperhaben), many have been concerned to remind us that we owe this conceptual distinction to the philosophical anthropologist Helmuth Plessner. He introduces the distinction in an essay from 1925—written in collaboration with the Dutch behavioral researcher Frederick Jacob Buytendijk—“Die Deutung des mimischen Ausdrucks. Ein Beitrag zur Lehre vom Bewusstsein des anderen (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant on biological teleology: Towards a two-level interpretation.Marcel Quarfood - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):735-747.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Die Stufen des Organischen und der Mensch.[author unknown] - 1928 - Annalen der Philosophie Und Philosophischen Kritik 7:36-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Lived Human Body from the Perspective of the Shared World (Mitwelt).Gesa Lindemann & Millay Hyatt - 2010 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 24 (3):275-291.
    The lived body (Leib) in the phenomenological tradition tends to be thought as the living body of the acting and perceiving subject, which is then analyzed by way of subjective self-reflection. This is true for Husserl (1970) as well as for Merleau-Ponty (1962) and Sartre (1992). When, however, the lived body is made the starting point of analysis in this way, it becomes a general and thus transhistorical condition of experience, and it is only in a second step that social (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (1 other version)Mechanical explanation of nature and its limits in Kant’s Critique of judgment.Angela Breitenbach - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):694-711.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (2 other versions)2. Kant über das Prinzip der Einheit von theoretischer und praktischer Philosophie (Einleitung I–V).Jochen Bojanowski - 2008 - In Otfried Höffe (ed.), Immanuel Kant. "Kritik der Urteilskraft". Boston: Akademie Verlag / De Gruyter. pp. 23-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Teleology then and now: The question of Kant’s relevance for contemporary controversies over function in biology.John Zammito - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):748-770.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Die Stufen des Organischen und der Mensch: Einleitung in die philosophische Anthropologie.Helmuth Plessner - 1981 - Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
    Frontmatter -- VORWORT ZUR ERSTEN AUFLAGE -- VORWORT ZUR ZWEITEN AUFLAGE -- INHALT -- Erstes Kapitel. ZIEL UND GEGENSTAND DER UNTERSUCHUNG -- Zweites Kapitel. DER CARTESIANISCHE EINWAND UND DIE PROBLEMSTELLUNG -- Drittes Kapitel. DIE THESE -- Viertes Kapitel. DIE DASEINSWEISEN DER LEBENDIGKEIT -- Fünftes Kapitel. DIE ORGANISATIONSWEISEN DES LEBENDIGEN DASEINS. PFLANZE UND TIER -- Sechstes Kapitel. DIE SPHÄRE DES TIERES -- Siebentes Kapitel: Die Sphaere des Menschen -- NACHTRAG -- SACHREGISTER -- NAMENSREGISTER -- Backmatter.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Die Bestimmung des Menschen bei Kant (Georg Geismann).Reinhard Brandt - 2007 - Philosophischer Literaturanzeiger 61 (1):4.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • (1 other version)Critique of Pure Reason.Wolfgang Schwarz - 1966 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 26 (3):449-451.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   678 citations  
  • (2 other versions)15. Von der Eigentümlichkeit unseres Verstands in Ansehung der Urteilskraft (§§ 74–78).Eckart Förster - 2008 - In Otfried Höffe (ed.), Immanuel Kant. "Kritik der Urteilskraft". Boston: Akademie Verlag / De Gruyter. pp. 259-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (2 other versions)13. Die Teleologie der organischen Natur (§§ 64–68).Ina Goy - 2008 - In Otfried Höffe (ed.), Immanuel Kant. "Kritik der Urteilskraft". Boston: Akademie Verlag / De Gruyter. pp. 223-239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Helmuth Plessner: Genese und System seines philosophisch-anthropologischen Denkens.Stephan Pietrowicz - 1992
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Die Teleologie der Natur (§§ 64–68).Ina Goy - 2008 - In Otfried Höffe (ed.), Immanuel Kant. "Kritik der Urteilskraft". Boston: Akademie Verlag / De Gruyter. pp. 223–239.
    A commentary on §§ 64-68 of Kant's "Critique of the Power of Judgment". Nach einer allgemeinen Definition von zweckmäßigen Gegenständen und deren Binnendifferenzierung in künstliche und natürliche Zwecke, setzt Kant in § 64 mit einer vorläufigen Definition des eigentlichen Untersuchungsgegenstandes ein. Dinge sind genau dann Naturzwecke, wenn sie von sich selbst Ursache und Wirkung sind. Kant veranschaulicht diese Definition am Beispiel eines organischen Gegenstandes: an einem Baum. In § 65 soll die vorläufige Definition von Naturzwecken präzisiert und von einem bestimmten (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation