Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (3 other versions)Freedom of the will and the concept of a person.Harry G. Frankfurt - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):5-20.
    It is my view that one essential difference between persons and other creatures is to be found in the structure of a person's will. Besides wanting and choosing and being moved to do this or that, men may also want to have certain desires and motives. They are capable of wanting to be different, in their preferences and purposes, from what they are. Many animals appear to have the capacity for what I shall call "first-order desires" or "desires of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1520 citations  
  • Against Parsimony: Three Easy Ways of Complicating some Categories of Economic Discourse.Albert O. Hirschman - 1985 - Economics and Philosophy 1 (1):7-21.
    Economics as a science of human behavior has been grounded in a remarkably parsimonious postulate: that of the self-interested, isolated individual who chooses freely and rationally between alternative courses of action after computing their prospective costs and benefits. In recent decades, a group of economists has shown considerable industry and ingenuity in applying this way of interpreting the social world to a series of ostensibly noneconomic phenomena, from crime to the family, and from collective action to democracy. The “economic” or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • A Methodological Assessment of Multiple Utility Frameworks.Timothy J. Brennan - 1989 - Economics and Philosophy 5 (2):189-208.
    One of the fundamental components of the concept of economic rationality is that preference orderings are “complete,” i.e., that all alternative actions an economic agent can take are comparable. The idea that all actions can be ranked may be called the single utility assumption. The attractiveness of this assumption is considerable. It would be hard to fathom what choice among alternatives means if the available alternatives cannot be ranked by the chooser in some way. In addition, the efficiency criterion makes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Social Norms, The Invisible Hand, and the Law.Jonny Anomaly & Geoffrey Brennan - 2014 - University of Queensland Law Journal 33 (2).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Plural Utility.Amartya Sen - 1981 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 81:193 - 215.
    Amartya Sen; XII*—Plural Utility, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 81, Issue 1, 1 June 1981, Pages 193–216, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • "Utility".John Broome - 1991 - Economics and Philosophy 7 (1):1-12.
    “Utility,” in plain English, means usefulness. In Australia, a ute is a useful vehicle. Jeremy Bentham specialized the meaning to a particular sort of usefulness. “By utility,” he said, “is meant that property in any object, whereby it tends to produce benefit, advantage, pleasure, good, or happiness or to prevent the happening of mischief, pain, evil, or unhappiness to the party whose interest is considered”. The “principle of utility” is the principle that actions are to be judged by their usefulness (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The diversity of goods.Charles Taylor - 1982 - In Amartya Sen & Bernard Williams (eds.), Utilitarianism and Beyond. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 129--135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • The Case for a Multiple-Utility Conception.Amitai Etzioni - 1986 - Economics and Philosophy 2 (2):159.
    In recent decades, neoclassical economists have made heroic efforts to accommodate within the confines of the concept of rational utility maximization the fact that individual behavior is significantly affected by moral considerations. This article argues the merits of using an alternative approach: recognizing that individuals pursue at least two irreducible sources of value or “utility”, pleasure and morality. The possibility that some additional utilities may have to be recognized is explored. This raises the concern that conceptual anarchy will break out, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Ethics, economics, and the state.Alan P. Hamlin - 1986 - New York: St. Martin's Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Review of Amitai Etzioni: The Moral Dimension: Toward a New Economics[REVIEW]Hamish Stewart - 1990 - Ethics 101 (1):205-206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Weakness of Will and the Free-Rider Problem.Jon Elster - 1985 - Economics and Philosophy 1 (2):231-265.
    The study of intrapersonal economic relations, or economics , is still at the programmatic stage. There is no generally accepted paradigm, or even as well-defined set of problems that constitute it as a subdiscipline within economics. Some questions are, however, emerging as foci of interest for a small but increasing number of writers, not just in economics, but also in psychology and philosophy. The writings of Thomas Schelling on self-management, of George Ainslie on self-control, and of Derik Parfit on personal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Beyond economic man: humanistic economics.Mark A. Lutz - 1985 - In Peter Koslowski (ed.), Economics and philosophy. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr. pp. 91--120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations