Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. La Science et l'Hypothèse.Henri Poincaré - 1902 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 11 (1):1-1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • The Rise of Scientific Philosophy.Hans Reichenbach - 1951 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 2 (8):334-337.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  • Dynamics of Reason.Michael Friedman - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (3):702-712.
    This book introduces a new approach to the issue of radical scientific revolutions, or "paradigm-shifts," given prominence in the work of Thomas Kuhn. The book articulates a dynamical and historicized version of the conception of scientific a priori principles first developed by the philosopher Immanuel Kant. This approach defends the Enlightenment ideal of scientific objectivity and universality while simultaneously doing justice to the revolutionary changes within the sciences that have since undermined Kant's original defense of this ideal. Through a modified (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   239 citations  
  • The definition of rigidity in the special theory of relativity and the genesis of the general theory of relativity.Giulio Maltese & Lucia Orlando - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 26 (3):263-306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A new semantics for the epistemology of geometry I: Modeling spacetime structure. [REVIEW]Robert Alan Coleman & Herbert Korté - 1995 - Erkenntnis 42 (2):141 - 160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Poincaré's conventionalism and the logical positivists.Michael Friedman - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (2):299-314.
    The logical positivists adopted Poincare's doctrine of the conventionality of geometry and made it a key part of their philosophical interpretation of relativity theory. I argue, however, that the positivists deeply misunderstood Poincare's doctrine. For Poincare's own conception was based on the group-theoretical picture of geometry expressed in the Helmholtz-Lie solution of the space problem, and also on a hierarchical picture of the sciences according to which geometry must be presupposed be any properly physical theory. But both of this pictures (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Space and Time in Contemporary Physics.Moritz Schlick - 1966 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 28 (2):379-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science.H. Weyl & Olaf Helmar - 1951 - Science and Society 15 (1):85-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Relativity and Geometry.R. Torretti - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (1):100-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • Philosophy of Physics.Roberto Torretti - 2001 - Erkenntnis 55 (1):127-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Relativity. The Special and General Theory.J. E. Trevor, Albert Einstein & Robert W. Lawson - 1921 - Philosophical Review 30 (2):213.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Riemanns frühe Notizen zum Mannigfaltigkeitsbegriff und zu den Grundlagen der Geometrie.E. Scholz - 1982 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 27 (3):213-232.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Hermann Weyls Analysis of the Problem of Space and the Origin of Gauge Structures.Erhard Scholz - 2004 - Science in Context 17 (1-2):165-197.
    Hermann Weyl was one of the early contributors to the mathematics of general relativity. This article argues that in 1929, for the formulation of a general relativistic framework of the Dirac equation, he both abolished and preserved in modified form the conceptual perspective that he had developed earlier in his “analysis of the problem of space.” The ideas of infinitesimal congruence from the early 1920s were aufgehoben in the general relativistic framework for the Dirac equation. He preserved the central idea (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Einstein and Duhem.Don Howard - 1990 - Synthese 83 (3):363-384.
    Pierre Duhem's often unrecognized influence on twentieth-century philosophy of science is illustrated by an analysis of his significant if also largely unrecognized influence on Albert Einstein. Einstein's first acquaintance with Duhem's La Théorie physique, son objet et sa structure around 1909 is strongly suggested by his close personal and professional relationship with Duhem's German translator, Friedrich Adler. The central role of a Duhemian holistic, underdeterminationist variety of conventionalism in Einstein's thought is examined at length, with special emphasis on Einstein's deployment (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The definition of rigidity in the special theory of relativity and the genesis of the general theory of relativity.Giulio Maltese & Lucia Orlando - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 26 (3):263-306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Interactions between mechanics and differential geometry in the 19th century.Jesper Lützen - 1995 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 49 (1):1-72.
    79. This study of the interaction between mechanics and differential geometry does not pretend to be exhaustive. In particular, there is probably more to be said about the mathematical side of the history from Darboux to Ricci and Levi Civita and beyond. Statistical mechanics may also be of interest and there is definitely more to be said about Hertz (I plan to continue in this direction) and about Poincaré's geometric and topological reasonings for example about the three body problem [Poincaré (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hermann von Helmholtz.Leo Koenigsberger, Lord Kelvin & Frances A. Welby - 1907 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 4 (26):715-717.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The Foundations of Geometry and the Concept of Motion: Helmholtz and Poincaré.Gerhard Heinzmann - 2001 - Science in Context 14 (3):457-470.
    ArgumentAccording to Hermann von Helmholtz, free mobility of bodies seemed to be an essential condition of geometry. This free mobility can be interpreted either as matter of fact, as a convention, or as a precondition making measurements in geometry possible. Since Henri Poincaré defined conventions as principles guided by experience, the question arises in which sense experiential data can serve as the basis for the constitution of geometry. Helmholtz considered muscular activity to be the basis on which the form of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The meaning of matter and the laws of nature according to the theory of relativity.A. S. Eddington - 1920 - Mind 29 (114):145-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Constructing or completing physical geometry? On the relation between theory and evidence in accounts of space-time structure.Martin Carrier - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (3):369-394.
    The aim of this paper is to discuss the relation between the observation basis and the theoretical principles of General Relativity. More specifically, this relation is analyzed with respect to constructive axiomatizations of the observation basis of space-time theories, on the one hand, and in attempts to complete them, on the other. The two approaches exclude one another so that a choice between them is necessary. I argue that the completeness approach is preferable for methodological reasons.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • How Weyl stumbled across electricity while pursuing mathematical justice.Alexander Afriat - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 40 (1):20-25.
    It is argued that Weyl’s theory of gravitation and electricity came out of ‘mathematical justice’: out of the equal rights direction and length. Such mathematical justice was manifestly at work in the context of discovery, and is enough to derive all of source-free electromagnetism. Weyl’s repeated references to coordinates and gauge are taken to express equal treatment of direction and length.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Open World. Three Lectures on the Metaphysical Implications of Science.Hermann Weyl - 1932 - Philosophy 7 (28):479-480.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mind and Nature.Hermann Weyl - 1935 - Philosophical Review 44:404.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Mathematische analyse des Raum problems.Hermann Weyl - 1923 - Annalen der Philosophie Und Philosophischen Kritik 4 (6):59-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations