Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Three kinds of rationalism and the non-spatiality of things in themselves.Desmond Hogan - 2009 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (3):pp. 355-382.
    In the transcendental aesthetic of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant claims that space and time are neither things in themselves nor properties of things in themselves but mere subjective forms of our sensible experience. Call this the Subjectivity Thesis. The striking conclusion follows an analysis of the representations of space and time. Kant argues that the two representations function as a priori conditions of experience, and are singular "intuitions" rather than general concepts. He also contends that the representations underwrite (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Kant, Real Possibility, and the Threat of Spinoza.Andrew Chignell - 2012 - Mind 121 (483):635-675.
    In the first part of the paper I reconstruct Kant’s proof of the existence of a ‘most real being’ while also highlighting the theory of modality that motivates Kant’s departure from Leibniz’s version of the proof. I go on to argue that it is precisely this departure that makes the being that falls out of the pre-critical proof look more like Spinoza’s extended natura naturans than an independent, personal creator-God. In the critical period, Kant seems to think that transcendental idealism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • (2 other versions)A causal theory of knowing.Alvin I. Goldman - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (12):357-372.
    Since Edmund L. Gettier reminded us recently of a certain important inadequacy of the traditional analysis of "S knows that p," several attempts have been made to correct that analysis. In this paper I shall offer still another analysis (or a sketch of an analysis) of "S knows that p," one which will avert Gettier's problem. My concern will be with knowledge of empirical propositions only, since I think that the traditional analysis is adequate for knowledge of nonempirical truths.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   385 citations  
  • The Neglected Alternative: Trendelenburg, Fischer, and Kant.Graham Bird - 2006 - In A Companion to Kant. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 486–499.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Central Issues in the Historical Dispute Resolving Issues over Kant's Position Kant's Arguments for his Claims.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant’s Argument for the Non-Spatiotemporality of Things in Themselves.Lorne Falkenstein - 1989 - Kant Studien 80 (1-4):265-83.
    Kant's problematic conclusion, that we can know that things in themselves are not in space or time, is shown to follow directly from his claim that space and time are manners of disposition or forms of arrangement in which various items are presented to us in intuition. This argument is not strong enough to rule out certain well-defined senses in which things in themselves "could" possibly be spatio-temporal, but it does show that any sense in which things in themselves could (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Spinoza and the a priori.Jon Miller - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (4):555-590.
    Scorned by analytic philosophers for much of the twentieth Century, thea priorihas been newly befriended in recent years. This development is healthy but there is reason to be concerned about how it is unfolding. In particular, it is largely characterized by a certain historical myopia: contemporary philosophers are able to see back to Kant but not much beyond him. While it may be true that thea priorichanged with Kant, this in itself provides us with a reason to go back before (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Space and Incongruence: The Origin of Kant's Idealism.Jill Vance Buroker - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (2):346-348.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Kant's Transcendental Psychology.Ralf Meerbote & Patricia Kitcher - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):862.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • La notion d'a priori chez Descartes et les philosophes médiévaux.Martin Pickave - 2005 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 75 (4):433.
    Cet article essaie de démontrer que le discours cartésien sur l’a priori est tributaire de la tradition philosophique antérieure et en particulier de la tradition médiévale. Selon cette dernière, l’expression a priori est strictement liée à un certain type de démonstration. Cette interprétation n’est pas contredite par les emplois que Descartes fait de l’expression a priori dans le traitement de deux thèmes clés de son œuvre : ses remarques sur l’ordre des raisons dans ses Méditations et sa présentation d’une des (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (3 other versions)Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist.Robert Merrihew Adams - 1994 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Adams presents an in-depth interpretation of three important parts of Leibniz's metaphysics, thoroughly grounded in the texts as well as in philosophical analysis and critique. The three areas discussed are the metaphysical part of Leibniz's philosophy of logic, his essentially theological treatment of the central issues of ontology, and his theory of substance. Adams' work helps make sense of one of the great classic systems of modern philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Kant and the Critique of Pure Reason.Sebastian Gardner - 1999 - New York: Routledge.
    Kant's _Critique of Pure Reason_ is arguably the single most important work in western philosophy. The book introduces and assesses: * Kant's life and background of the _Critique of Pure Reason_ * the ideas and text of the _Critique of Pure Reason_ * the continuing relevance of Kant's work to contemporary philosophy. Ideal for anyone coming to Kant's thought for the first time. This guide will be vital reading for all students of Kant in philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Bounds of Sense.P. F. Strawson - 1966 - Philosophy 42 (162):379-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   402 citations  
  • Grundsätze der reinen Philosophie.Christian Gottlieb Selle - 1788 - [Bruxelles,: Culture et Civilisation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Space as Form of Intuition and as Formal Intuition: On the Note to B160 in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.Christian Onof & Dennis Schulting - 2015 - Philosophical Review 124 (1):1-58.
    In his argument for the possibility of knowledge of spatial objects, in the Transcendental Deduction of the B-version of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant makes a crucial distinction between space as “form of intuition” and space as “formal intuition.” The traditional interpretation regards the distinction between the two notions as reflecting a distinction between indeterminate space and determinations of space by the understanding, respectively. By contrast, a recent influential reading has argued that the two notions can be fused into (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • F. A. Trendelenburg and the Neglected Alternative.Andrew Specht - 2014 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (3):514-534.
    Despite his impressive influence on nineteenth-century philosophy, F. A. Trendelenburg's own philosophy has been largely ignored. However, among Kant scholars, Trendelenburg has always been remembered for his feud with Kuno Fischer over the subjectivity of space and time in Kant's philosophy. The topic of the dispute, now frequently referred to as the ?Neglected Alternative? objection, has become a prominent issue in contemporary discussions and interpretations of Kant's view of space and time. The Neglected Alternative contends that Kant unjustifiably moves from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kant's Only Possible Argument and Chignell's Real Harmony.Uygar Abaci - 2014 - Kantian Review 19 (1):1-25.
    Andrew Chignell recently proposed an original reconstruction of Kant's ‘Only Possible Argument’ for the existence of God. Chignell claims that what motivates the ‘Grounding Premise’ of Kant's proof, ‘real possibility must be grounded in actuality’, is the requirement that the predicates of a really possible thing must be ‘really harmonious’, i.e. compatible in an extra-logical or metaphysical sense. I take issue with Chignell's reconstruction. First, the pre-Critical Kant does not present ‘real harmony’ as a general condition of real possibility. Second, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • God, Totality and Possibility in Kant's Only Possible Argument.Peter Yong - 2014 - Kantian Review 19 (1):27-51.
    There has been a groundswell of interest in the account of modality that Kant sets forth in his pre-Critical Only Possible Argument. Andrew Chignell's reconstruction of Kant's theistic argument in terms of what he calls has a prima facie advantage in that it appears to be able to block the plurality objection (namely, that even if every modal fact presupposes some ground, this does not entail that all modal facts share the same ground). I argue that it is both textually (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Ideality of Space and Time: Trendelenburg versus Kant, Fischer and Bird.Edward Kanterian - 2013 - Kantian Review 18 (2):263-288.
    Trendelenburg argued that Kant's arguments in support of transcendental idealism ignored the possibility that space and time are both ideal and real. Recently, Graham Bird has claimed that Trendelenburg (unlike his contemporary Kuno Fischer) misrepresented Kant, confusing two senses of . I defend Trendelenburg's : the ideas of space and time, as a priori and necessary, are ideal, but this does not exclude their validity in the noumenal realm. This undermines transcendental idealism. Bird's attempt to show that the Analytic considers, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The neo‐kantianRaumcontroversy.Christopher Adair‐Toteff - 1994 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 2 (2):131-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Spinoza and the "A Priori".Jon Miller - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (4):555 - 590.
    Scorned by analytic philosophers for much of the twentieth century, the a priori has been newly befriended in recent years. This development is healthy but there is reason to be concerned about how it is unfolding. In particular, it is largely characterized by a certain historical myopia: contemporary philosophers are able to see back to Kant but not much beyond him. While it may be true that the a priori changed with Kant, this in itself provides us with a reason (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kant's Possibility Proof.Nicholas Stang - 2010 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 27 (3):275-299.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Apriority, reason, and induction in Hume.Houston Smit - 2010 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (3):313-343.
    In what follows, I argue that Hume works with a notion of the a priori that, though unfamiliar today, was standard in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. On this notion of the a priori, to know (consider, prove) something a priori is to know (consider, prove) it from the grounds that make it true. I will refer to this as the "from-grounds" notion of the a priori, and to the now-familiar and dominant notion—on which to know something a priori is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The neo-Kantian raum controversy.Christopher Adair-Toteff - 1994 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 2 (2):131 – 148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant on Apriority and the Spontaneity of Cognition.Houston Smit - 2009 - In Samuel Newlands & Larry M. Jorgensen (eds.), Metaphysics and the good: themes from the philosophy of Robert Merrihew Adams. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant and the apriority of space.Daniel Warren - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (2):179-224.
    In interpretations of the "Transcendental Aesthetic" section of the first Critique, there is a widespread tendency to present Kant as establishing that the representation of space is a condition for individuating or distinguishing objects, and to claim that it is on this basis that Kant establishes the apriority of this representation. The aim of this paper is to criticize this way of interpreting the "Aesthetic," and to defend an alternative interpretation. On this alternative, questions about the formation of the representation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Mr. Russell's causal theory of perception.M. H. A. Newman - 1928 - Mind 37 (146):26-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   147 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant.Eric Watkins - 2009 - In Helen Beebee, Christopher Hitchcock & Peter Menzies (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Causation. Oxford University Press UK.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • The non-spatiality of things in themselves for Kant.Henry E. Allison - 1976 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 14 (3):313-321.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Kant.Patricia Kitcher, Philip Kitcher & Ralph C. S. Walker - 1980 - Philosophical Review 89 (2):282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason.".P. R. Strawson, Jonathan Bennett, D. P. Dryer & Arnulf Zweig - 1967 - Ethics 78 (1):89-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Weg zur Gewißheit und Zuverlässigkeit der menschlichen Erkenntnis (Logik).Christian August Crusius - 1747 - Johann Friedrich Gleditsch.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Die Logik der Neuzeit.Wilhelm Risse - 1964 - Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt,: F. Frommann.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Transcendental Ideality of Space and the Neglected Alternative.Peter Herissone-Kelly - 2007 - Kant Studien 98 (3):269-282.
    In the Transcendental Aesthetic, Kant famously makes the following startling claim, which we can call the transcendental ideality thesis concerning the nature of space, or, for ease of reference in what follows, simply “TI”: Der Raum stellt gar keine Eigenschaft irgend einiger Dinge an sich, oder sie in ihrem Verhältniß auf einander vor, d.i. keine Bestimmung derselben, die an Gegenständen selbst haftete, und welche bliebe, wenn man auch von allen subjectiven Bedingungen der Anschauung abstrahirte.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations