Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Language, Truth, and Logic.A. J. Ayer - 1936 - Philosophy 23 (85):173-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   778 citations  
  • A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge.George Berkeley - 1901 - The Monist 11:637.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   326 citations  
  • An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding.David Hume - 1901 - The Monist 11:312.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   971 citations  
  • I—Peter Millican: Humes Old and New Four Fashionable Falsehoods, and One Unfashionable Truth.Peter Millican & Helen Beebee - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):163-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Two Definitions of ‘cause,’ Newton, and The Significance of the Humean Distinction Between Natural and Philosophical Relations.Eric Schliesser - 2007 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 5 (1):83-101.
    The main aim of this paper is to explore why it is so important for Hume to defi ne ‘cause’ as he does. This will shed light on the signifi cance of the natural/philosophical relation (hereafter NPR) distinction in the Treatise. Hume's use of the NPR distinction allows him to dismiss on general grounds conceptions of causation at odds with his own. In particular, it allows him to avoid having to engage in detailed re-interpretation of potentially confl icting theories formulated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Hume’s Absolute Necessity.Thomas Holden - 2014 - Mind 123 (490):377-413.
    Hume regards the ‘absolute’ necessity attending demonstrable propositions as an expression of the limitations of human imagination. When we register our modal commitments in ordinary descriptive language, affirming that there are such-and-such absolute necessities, possibilities, and impossibilities, we are projecting our sense of what the human mind can and cannot conceive. In some ways the account parallels Hume’s famous treatment of the necessity of causes, and in some respects it anticipates recent expressivist theories of absolute modality. I marshal the evidence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Hume’s Two Definitions: The Procedural Interpretation.Helen Beebee - 2011 - Hume Studies 37 (2):243-274.
    Hume's two definitions of causation have caused an extraordinary amount of controversy. The starting point for the controversy is the fact, well known to most philosophy undergraduates, that the two definitions aren't even extensionally equivalent, let alone semantically equivalent. So how can they both be definitions? One response to this problem has been to argue that Hume intends only the first as a genuine definition—an interpretation that delivers a straightforward regularity interpretation of Hume on causation. By many commentators' lights, however, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Two Definitions and the Doctrine of Necessity.Helen Beebee - 2007 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 107 (1pt3):413-431.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Conceivability and modality in Hume: A lemma in an argument in defense of skeptical realism.Peter Kail - 2003 - Hume Studies 29 (1):43--61.
    This paper examines the ramifications of Hume's view of the relation of conceivability to metaphysical possibility. It argues that the limitations Hume places of the representations involved in moves to conceivability to metaphysical possibility preclude any straightforward argument against full-blooded causal realism in Hume from conceivability. Furthermore, our finding certain states of affairs conceivable when they are not metaphysically possible is perfectly compatible with the thrust of the causal realist position.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Conceptual truth.Timothy Williamson - 2006 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80 (1):1–41.
    The paper criticizes epistemological conceptions of analytic or conceptual truth, on which assent to such truths is a necessary condition of understanding them. The critique involves no Quinean scepticism about meaning. Rather, even granted that a paradigmatic candidate for analyticity is synonymy with a logical truth, both the former and the latter can be intelligibly doubted by linguistically competent deviant logicians, who, although mistaken, still constitute counterexamples to the claim that assent is necessary for understanding. There are no analytic or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • De re senses.John Mcdowell - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (136):283-294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   197 citations  
  • What is it like to be a bat?Thomas Nagel - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (October):435-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2218 citations  
  • Twenty Questions about Hume's “Of Miracles”.Peter Millican - 2011 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 68:151-192.
    Hume's essay on the credibility of miracle reports has always been controversial, with much debate over how it should be interpreted, let alone assessed. My aim here is to summarise what I take to be the most plausible views on these issues, both interpretative and philosophical, with references to facilitate deeper investigation if desired. The paper is divided into small sections, each headed by a question that provides a focus. Broadly speaking, §§1–3 and §20 are on Hume's general philosophical framework (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Locke, Berkeley, Hume: Central Themes.Jonathan Bennett - 1971 - Philosophy 47 (180):175-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Naming and Necessity.Saul Kripke - 1980 - Critica 17 (49):69-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1824 citations  
  • The Powers and Mechanisms of the Passions.Lilli Alanen - 2006 - In Saul Traiger (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Hume’s Treatise. Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 179–198.
    This chapter contains section titled: Introductory Remarks The Cartesian Background Impressions and Ideas Passions as Reflective Impressions Direct and Indirect Passions Association and the Individuation of Passions Perception and Perceiving Passions and Moral Sentiments Notes References Further reading.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Hume on Conceivability and Inconceivability.D. Tycerium Lightner - 1997 - Hume Studies 23 (1):113-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Kant, Hume and Analyticity.Donald Gotterbarn - 1974 - Kant Studien 65 (1-4):274-283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Analyticity Again.Jerry Fodor & Ernie Lepore - 2006 - In Michael Devitt & Richard Hanley (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language. Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 19--114.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction Analyticity and Meaning Realism Logical Truths Conclusion Addendum.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Apriority, reason, and induction in Hume.Houston Smit - 2010 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (3):313-343.
    In what follows, I argue that Hume works with a notion of the a priori that, though unfamiliar today, was standard in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. On this notion of the a priori, to know (consider, prove) something a priori is to know (consider, prove) it from the grounds that make it true. I will refer to this as the "from-grounds" notion of the a priori, and to the now-familiar and dominant notion—on which to know something a priori is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hume, causal realism, and causal science.Peter Millican - 2009 - Mind 118 (471):647-712.
    The ‘New Hume’ interpretation, which sees Hume as a realist about ‘thick’ Causal powers, has been largely motivated by his evident commitment to causal language and causal science. In this, however, it is fundamentally misguided, failing to recognise how Hume exploits his anti-realist conclusions about (upper-case) Causation precisely to support (lower-case) causal science. When critically examined, none of the standard New Humean arguments — familiar from the work of Wright, Craig, Strawson, Buckle, Kail, and others — retains any significant force (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Content, Thoughts, and Definite Descriptions.Peter Millican - 1990 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 64 (1):167 - 220.
    In this paper,[1] I shall address the much-discussed issue of how definite descriptions should be analysed: whether they should be given a quantificational analysis in the style of Russell’s theory of descriptions,[2] or whether they should be seen instead, at least in some cases, as “genuine singular terms” or “genuine referring expressions”, whose function is to pick out a particular object in order to say something about that very object.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A priori knowledge for fallibilists.Aron Edidin - 1984 - Philosophical Studies 46 (2):189 - 197.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Modest a priori knowledge.Donna M. Summerfield - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1):39-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Notes on existence and necessity.Willard V. Quine - 1943 - Journal of Philosophy 40 (5):113-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Propositional content.Stephen Schiffer - 2005 - In Ernie Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    To a first approximation, _propositional content_ is whatever _that-clauses_ contribute to what is ascribed in utterances of sentences such as Ralph believes _that Tony Curtis is alive_. Ralph said _that Tony Curtis is alive_. Ralph hopes _that Tony Curtis is alive_. Ralph desires _that Tony Curtis is alive_.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • What is it like to be a bat?Thomas Nagel - 1979 - In Mortal questions. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 435 - 450.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1462 citations  
  • Probability and Hume's Inductive Scepticism.D. C. Stove - 1973 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 35 (3):646-647.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Locke, Berkeley, Hume: Central Themes.Jonathan Bennett - 1971 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (4):691-701.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • An Essay Concerning Human Understanding.John Locke - 1979 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 169 (2):221-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   670 citations  
  • A Dictionary of Philosophy.Antony Flew - 1979 - Religious Studies 15 (4):582-582.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • The Sceptical Realism of David Hume.John P. Wright - 1983 - Behaviorism 15 (2):175-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Hume's 'scepticism'about induction.Peter Millican - 2012 - In Alan Bailey & Dan O'Brien (eds.), The Continuum Companion to Hume. Continuum.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • An Essay concerning Human Understanding.John Locke & Alexander Campbell Fraser - 1894 - Mind 3 (12):536-543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   389 citations  
  • Hume's two definitions of "cause".J. A. Robinson - 1962 - Philosophical Quarterly 12 (47):162-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Propositional Attitude Ascription.Mark Richard - 2006 - In Michael Devitt & Richard Hanley (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language. Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 186–211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Abstract Objects.Bob Hale - 1987 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 179 (1):109-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • I—Peter Millican: Humes Old and New Four Fashionable Falsehoods, and One Unfashionable Truth.Peter Millican - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):163-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Introduction.Tamar Szabo Gendler & John Hawthorne - 2002 - In Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • Hume's theory of relations.Alan Hausman - 1967 - Noûs 1 (3):255-282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Kant's conception of "Hume's problem".Manfred Kuehn - 1983 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 21 (2):175-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Probability and Hume's Inductive Scepticism.David Charles Stove - 1973 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    This book aims to discuss probability and David Hume's inductive scepticism. For the sceptical view which he took of inductive inference, Hume only ever gave one argument. That argument is the sole subject-matter of this book. The book is divided into three parts. Part one presents some remarks on probability. Part two identifies Hume's argument for inductive scepticism. Finally, the third part evaluates Hume's argument for inductive scepticism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Conceptual Truth.Timothy Williamson - 2006 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80 (1):1-41.
    The paper criticizes epistemological conceptions of analytic or conceptual truth, on which assent to such truths is a necessary condition of understanding them. The critique involves no Quinean scepticism about meaning. Rather, even granted that a paradigmatic candidate for analyticity is synonymy with a logical truth, both the former and the latter can be intelligibly doubted by linguistically competent deviant logicians, who, although mistaken, still constitute counterexamples to the claim that assent is necessary for understanding. There are no analytic or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • 11. “Two Definitions of ‘Cause,’ Newton, and the Significance of the Humean distinction between Natural and Philosophical Relations,”.Eric Schliesser - 2007 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 5 (1):83-101.
    The main aim of this paper is to explore why it is so important for Hume to defi ne ‘cause’ as he does. This will shed light on the signifi cance of the natural/philosophical relation (hereafter NPR) distinction in the Treatise. Hume's use of the NPR distinction allows him to dismiss on general grounds conceptions of causation at odds with his own. In particular, it allows him to avoid having to engage in detailed re-interpretation of potentially confl icting theories formulated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hume's Philosophy of Belief.Antony Flew - 1961 - Philosophy 39 (147):88-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Hume on Conceivability and Inconceivability.D. Tycerium Lightner - 1997 - Hume Studies 23 (1):113-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Hume’s Mature Account of the Indirect Passions.Amyas Merivale - 2009 - Hume Studies 35 (1-2):185-210.
    Hume’s Dissertation on the Passions stands to Book 2 of his Treatise as the first and second Enquiries stand to Books 1 and 3 respectively. However, while the two Enquiries are evidently substantial reworkings of their Treatise ancestors, containing much that is different and new, the Dissertation appears to consist merely of superficially adapted excerpts from Treatise Book 2. I argue that this first impression is mistaken, by showing how Hume’s view of the indirect passions is modified in the later (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Sceptical Realism of David Hume.John P. Wright - 1983 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 47 (1):129-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy.Don Garrett - 1997 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 62 (1):191-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations  
  • The Supporting Arguments.Albert Casullo - 2003 - In A Priori Justification. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press USA.
    The leading arguments supporting the existence of a priori knowledge fall into three broad categories: conceptual arguments, which offer an analysis of the concept of a priori knowledge and maintain that some knowledge satisfies the conditions in the analysis; criterial arguments, which identify criteria of the a priori, such as necessity, certainty, and irrefutability, and maintain that some knowledge satisfies the criteria; and deficiency arguments, which allege that radical empiricist theories of knowledge are deficient in some respect, and that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations