Switch to: Citations

References in:

Inferentialism: why rules matter

New York: Palgrave-Macmillan (2014)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (2 other versions)Michael Dummett, Frege: Philosophy of Language. [REVIEW]Hidé Ishiguro - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (190):438-442.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   506 citations  
  • (1 other version)Concepts as Involving Laws and Inconceivable Without Them.Wilfrid Sellars - 1949 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 14 (1):59-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Symbolic Logic.C. I. Lewis & C. H. Langford - 1932 - Erkenntnis 4 (1):65-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   224 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Symbolic Logic.Clarence Irving Lewis & Cooper Harold Langford - 1934 - Mind 43 (169):99-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • (1 other version)Brandom's Burdens: Compositionality and Inferentialism. [REVIEW]Jerry Fodor & Ernie Lepore - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (2):465-481.
    Robert Brandom has it in mind to run a ‘pragmatist’ theory of content. That is, he wants to reconstruct notions like saying such and such or believing such and such in terms of a distinctive kind of “knowing how or being able to do something”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Pragmatics Of Inferential Content.Wolfram Hinzen - 2001 - Synthese 128 (1-2):157-181.
    Carnap took the content of a particularsentence or set of sentences to consist in the set ofthe consequences of the sentence or set. This claimequates meaning with inferential role, but itrestricts the inferences to deductive or explicativeones. Here I reject a recent proposal by RobertBrandom, where inductive or ampliative inferences arealso meant to confer contents on expressions. I arguethat if Brandom's inferentialist picture is upheld, andboth explicative and ampliative inferences confermeaning, one consequence of this is that the contentof a sentence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Language, Rules and Behavior.Wilfrid Sellars - 1950 - In Sidney Hook (ed.), John Dewey, philosopher of science and freedom: a symposium. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press. pp. 289–315.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Meaning and Structure.Jaroslav Peregrin - 2002 - Filosoficky Casopis 50:686-688.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Tales of the Mighty Dead.Jaroslav Peregrin - 2005 - Filosoficky Casopis 53 (3):782-785.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Developing Sellars's Semantic Legacy: Meaning as a Role.Jaroslav Peregrin - 2007 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 92 (1):257-274.
    Wilfrid Sellars's analysis of the concept of meaning led, in effect, to the conclusion that the meaning of an expression is its inferential role. This view is often challenged by the claim that inference is a matter of syntax and syntax can never yield us semantics. I argue that this challenge is based on the confusion of two senses of "syntax"; and I try to throw some new light on the concept of inferential role. My conclusion is that the Sellarsian (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Conjunction and Contonktion Revisited.A. N. Prior - 1964 - Analysis 24 (6):191 - 195.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Tonk, Plonk and Plink.Nuel Belnap - 1962 - Analysis 22 (6):130-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   207 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Why meaning (probably) isn't conceptual role.Jerry A. Fodor & Ernest Lepore - 2010 - In Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel (eds.), Arguing about language. New York: Routledge. pp. 15 - 35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)Frege: Philosophy of Language.Michael Dummett - 1973 - London: Duckworth.
    This highly acclaimed book is a major contribution to the philosophy of language as well as a systematic interpretation of Frege, indisputably the father of ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   848 citations  
  • Tales of the mighty dead: historical essays in the metaphysics of intentionality.Robert Brandom - 2002 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    A work in the history of systematic philosophy that is itself animated by a systematic philosophic aspiration, this book by one of the most prominent American ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   173 citations  
  • The taming of the true.Neil Tennant - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The Taming of the True poses a broad challenge to realist views of meaning and truth that have been prominent in recent philosophy. Neil Tennant argues compellingly that every truth is knowable, and that an effective logical system can be based on this principle. He lays the foundations for global semantic anti-realism and extends its consequences from the philosophy of mathematics and logic to the theory of meaning, metaphysics, and epistemology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   196 citations  
  • A dual-process specification of causal conditional reasoning.Niki Verschueren, Walter Schaeken & G. - 2005 - Thinking and Reasoning 11 (3):239 – 278.
    There are two accounts describing causal conditional reasoning: the probabilistic and the mental models account. According to the probabilistic account, the tendency to accept a conclusion is related to the probability by which cause and effect covary. According to the mental models account, the tendency to accept a conclusion relates to the availability of counterexamples. These two accounts are brought together in a dual-process theory: It is argued that the probabilistic reasoning process can be considered as a heuristic process whereas (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • ‘if p then q’... and all that: Logical Elements in Reasoning and Discourse. [REVIEW]Marian Counihan - 2008 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 17 (4):391-415.
    In this paper we explore differences in use of the so-called ‘logical’ elements of language such as quantifiers and conditionals, and use this to explain differences in performance in reasoning tasks across subject groups with different educational backgrounds. It is argued that quantified sentences are difficult natural bases for reasoning, and hence more prone to elicit variation in reasoning behaviour, because they are chiefly used with a pre-determined domain in everyday speech. By contrast, it is argued that conditional sentences form (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logical Rules and the a priori: Good and Bad Questions.Jaroslav Peregrin - 2007 - In Jean-Yves Béziau & Alexandre Costa-Leite (eds.), Perspectives on Universal Logic. Milan, Italy: Polimetrica. pp. 111--122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intersubstitutivity.Jaroslav Peregrin - manuscript
    Atomists explain properties of wholes as compositions of properties of their parts; in particular properties of complex expressions as composed of properties of their parts. Especially, semantic atomists explain meanings of complex expressions as composed of meanings of their parts. Holists deny themselves this way: they insist that at least in some cases properties of wholes are more basic than, or not reducible to, properties of their parts; in particular, semantic holists claim that meanings of (at least some) wholes are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Meaning as functional classification.Wilfrid Sellars - 1974 - Synthese 27 (3-4):417 - 437.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • (1 other version)Inference and meaning.Wilfrid Sellars - 1953 - Mind 62 (247):313-338.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Ontological relativity.W. V. O. Quine - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (7):185-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   356 citations  
  • A counterexample to modus ponens.Vann McGee - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy 82 (9):462-471.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   226 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Why meaning (probably) isn't conceptual role.J. A. Fodor & E. LePore - 1993 - Philosophical Issues 3:15-35.
    It's an achievement of the last couple of decades that people who work in linguistic semantics and people who work in the philosophy of language have arrived at a friendly, de facto agreement as to their respective job descriptions. The terms of this agreement are that the semanticists do the work and the philosophers do the worrying. The semanticists try to construct actual theories of meaning (or truth theories, or model theories, or whatever) for one or another kind of expression (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • (1 other version)Concepts as involving laws and inconceivable without them.Wilfrid Sellars - 1948 - Philosophy of Science 15 (October):287-313.
    Formal implication is usually represented by symbolization such as ‘ φx ⊃ Ψx,’ which may be read, “for all values of ‘x’, φx implies Ψx.” If the values of the variable ‘x’, in ‘φx’ and ‘Ψx’ be ‘x1’ ‘x2’ ‘x3’, etc., then … ‘φx’ formally implies ‘Ψx’ if and only if, whatever values of ‘x’, ‘xn’, be chosen, ‘φxn’ materially implies ‘Ψxn’ …However, this still leaves it doubtful which of two possible interpretations of expressions having the form ‘ φx ⊃ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • (1 other version)Wherein lies the normative dimension in meaning and mental content?Pascal Engel - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 100 (3):305-321.
    This paper argues that the normative dimension in mental and semantic content is not a categorical feature of content, but an hypothetical one, relative to the features of the interpretation of thoughts and meaning. The views of Robert Brandom are discussed. The thesis defended in this paper is not interpretationist about thought. It implies that the normative dimension of content arises from the real capacity of thinkers and speakers to self ascribe thoughts to themselves and to reach self knowledge of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Do inferential roles compose?Mark McCullagh - 2003 - Dialectica 57 (4):431-38.
    Jerry Fodor and Ernie Lepore have argued that inferential roles are not compositional. It is unclear, however, whether the theories at which they aim their objection are obliged to meet the strong compositionality requirement they have in mind. But even if that requirement is accepted, the data they adduce can in fact be derived from an inferential-role theory that meets it. Technically this is trivial, but it raises some interesting objections turning on the issue of the generality of inferential roles. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Meaning as an inferential role.Jaroslav Peregrin - 2006 - Erkenntnis 64 (1):1-35.
    While according to the inferentialists, meaning is always a kind of inferential role, proponents of other approaches to semantics often doubt that actual meanings, as they see them, can be generally reduced to inferential roles. In this paper we propose a formal framework for considering the hypothesis of the.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Why meaning (probably) isn't conceptual role.Jerry Fodor & Ernest Lepore - 1991 - Mind and Language 6 (4):328-43.
    It's an achievement of the last couple of decades that people who work in linguistic semantics and people who work in the philosophy of language have arrived at a friendly, de facto agreement as to their respective job descriptions. The terms of this agreement are that the semanticists do the work and the philosophers do the worrying. The semanticists try to construct actual theories of meaning (or truth theories, or model theories, or whatever) for one or another kind of expression (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Ontological Relativity.Willard van Orman Quine - 1969 - In Willard Van Orman Quine (ed.), Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press. pp. 26-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Making it Explicit.Isaac Levi & Robert B. Brandom - 1996 - Journal of Philosophy 93 (3):145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   961 citations  
  • Précis of M aking It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment.Robert Brandom & Robert B. Brandom - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (1):153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   208 citations  
  • Frege's content-principle and relevant deducibility.Neil Tennant - 2003 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (3):245-258.
    Given the harmony principle for logical operators, compositionality ought to ensure that harmony should obtain at the level of whole contents. That is, the role of a content qua premise ought to be balanced exactly by its role as a conclusion. Frege's contextual definition of propositional content happens to exploit this balance, and one appeals to the Cut rule to show that the definition is adequate. We show here that Frege's definition remains adequate even when one relevantizes logic by abandoning (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations