Switch to: Citations

References in:

Paul Feyerabend

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Feyerabend.John Preston - 2017 - In W. H. Newton‐Smith (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Science. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 143–148.
    Paul K. Feyerabend (1924–94) was an imaginative maverick philosopher of science, a critic of positivism, as well as, more recently, falsificationism, philosophy of science itself, and of “rationalist” attempts to lay down or discover rules of scientific method.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Correspondence, Invariance and Heuristics: In Praise of Conservative Induction.H. R. Post - 1971 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 2 (3):213.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • Goodbye and farewell: Siegel vs. Feyerabend.Alfred Nordmann - 1990 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 33 (3):317 – 331.
    In his review (Inquiry 32 [1989], pp. 343?69) of Paul Feyerabend's Farewell to Reason, Harvey Siegel makes a fairly simple point: Feyerabend provides a bad argument for a good cause. In particular, Siegel maintains that the argument suffers, first, from self?inflicted depreciation: having been rendered impotent by Feyerabend's views of objectivity and rationality, what claim to persuasion can his argument possibly hold? And second, the argument is said to be incoherent: instead of respecting and leaving alone diverse cultures and traditions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Teleology revisited and other essays in the philosophy and history of science.Ernest Nagel - 1979 - New York: Columbia University Press.
    Ernest Nagel, one of the world's leading philosophers of science, is an unreconstructed empirical rationalist who continues to believe that the logical methods of the modern natural sciences are the most successful instruments men have devised to acquire reliable knowledge. This book presents "Teleology Revisited"-the John Dewey lectures delivered at Columbia University- and eleven of Nagel's articles on the philosophy of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Historical antecedents to the philosophy of Paul Feyerabend.Gonzalo Munévar - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 57:9-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Are there rival, incommensurable theories?Dale W. Moberg - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (2):244-262.
    Following an account of the incommensurability argument, an objection, based on assumptions concerning rival theories, is examined and rejected. This rejection leads to an alternative direction of criticism of incommensurability, a direction that involves the articulation of comparative standards of theory evaluation that are independent of meaning invariance.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Against incommensurability.Michael Devitt - 1979 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 57 (1):29-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • “The Battle is on”: Lakatos, Feyerabend, and the student protests.Eric C. Martin - 2019 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 9 (2):1-33.
    This paper shows how late 1960’s student protests influenced the thought of Imre Lakatos and Paul Feyerabend. I argue that student movements shaped their work from this period, specifically Lakatos’s “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes” and Feyerabend’s Against Method. Archival evidence shows that their political environments at London and Berkeley inflected their writing on scientific method, entrenching Lakatos’s search for a rationalist account of scientific development, and encouraging Feyerabend’s ‘anarchistic’ theory of knowledge. I document this influence and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Late Feyerabend on materialism, mysticism, and religion.Eric C. Martin - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 57:129-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Feyerabend and Galileo: The interaction of theories, and the reinterpretation of experience.Peter K. Machamer - 1973 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 4 (1):1-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The anachronistic anarchist.Elisabeth A. Lloyd - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 81 (2-3):247 - 261.
    A reading of Feyerabend in Against Method, and a comparison of C.S. Peirce.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Feyerabend, mill, and pluralism.Elisabeth A. Lloyd - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (4):407.
    I suggest following Paul Feyerabend's own advice, and interpreting Feyerabend's work in light of the principles laid out by John Stuart Mill. A review of Mill's essay, On Liberty, emphasizes the importance Mill placed on open and critical discussion for the vitality and progress of various aspects of human life, including the pursuit of scientific knowledge. Many of Feyerabend's more unusual stances, I suggest, are best interpreted as attempts to play certain roles--especially the role of "defender of unpopular minority opinion"--that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Meaning variance and the comparability of theories.Jarrett Leplin - 1969 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20 (1):69-75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Feyerabend, brownian motion, and the hiddenness of refuting facts.Ronald Laymon - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (2):225-247.
    In this paper, I will develop a nontrivial interpretation of Feyerabend's concept of a hidden anomalous fact. Feyerabend's claim is that some anomalous facts will remain hidden in the absence of alternatives to the theories to be tested. The case of Brownian motion is given by Feyerabend to support this claim. The essential scientific difficulty in this case was the justification of correct and relevant descriptions of Brownian motion. These descriptions could not be simply determined from the available observational data. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Carnap, Feyerabend, and the Pragmatic Theory of Observation.Daniel Kuby - 2018 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 8 (2):432-470.
    Paul Feyerabend once made a remark to the effect that his pragmatic theory of observation can be traced back to proposals put forward by leading Logical Empiricists during the height of the protocol sentence debate. In this paper I want to vindicate the systematic side of Feyerabend’s remark and show that a pragmatic theory of observation can in fact be found in Rudolf Carnap’s writings of 1932. I first proceed to dispel a misunderstanding concerning the term “pragmatic” raised by Thomas (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Feyerabend unbound.Stephen Kresge - 1996 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 26 (2):293-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Feyerabend, Feminism, and Philosophy.Noretta Koertge - 2013 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 3 (1):139-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • For and against method. [REVIEW]Noretta Koertge - 1972 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23 (3):274-290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Feyerabend, Galileo and Darwin: How to Make the Best out of What You Have - or Think You Can Get.Scott A. Kleiner - 1979 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 10 (4):285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Why did Feyerabend Defend Astrology? Integrity, Virtue, and the Authority of Science.Ian James Kidd - 2016 - Social Epistemology 30 (4):464-482.
    This paper explores the relationship between epistemic integrity, virtue, and authority by offering a virtue epistemological reading of the defences of non-scientific beliefs, practices, and traditions in the writings of Paul Feyerabend. I argue that there was a robust epistemic rationale for those defences and that it can inform contemporary reflection on the epistemic authority of the sciences. Two common explanations of the purpose of those defences are rejected as lacking textual support. A third “pluralist” reading is judged more persuasive, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Was Feyerabend a Postmodernist?Ian James Kidd - 2016 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 30 (1):55-68.
    ABSTRACTThis article asks whether the philosophy of Paul K. Feyerabend can be reasonably classified as postmodernist, a label applied to him by friends and foes alike. After describing some superficial similarities between the style and content of both Feyerabend’s and postmodernist writings, I offer three more robust characterisations of postmodernism in terms of relativism, ‘incredulity to metanarratives’, and ‘depthlessness’. It emerges that none of these characterisations offers a strong justification for classifying Feyerabend as ‘postmodern’ in any significant sense. Indeed, what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Objectivity, abstraction, and the individual: The influence of Søren Kierkegaard on Paul Feyerabend.Ian James Kidd - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):125-134.
    This paper explores the influence of Søren Kierkegaard upon Paul Feyerabend by examining their common criticisms of totalising accounts of human nature. Both complained that philosophical and scientific theories of human nature which were methodologically committed to objectivity and abstraction failed to capture the richness of human experience. Kierkegaard and Feyerabend argued that philosophy and the science were threatening to become obstacles to human development by imposing abstract theories of human nature and reality which denied the complexities of both. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Feyerabend on politics, education, and scientific culture.Ian James Kidd - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 57:121-128.
    The purpose of this paper is to offer a sympathetic reconstruction of the political thought of Paul Feyerabend. Using a critical discussion of the idea of the ‘free society’ it is suggested that his political thought is best understood in terms of three thematic concerns – liberation, hegemony, and the authority of science – and that the political significance of those claims become clear when they are considered in the context of his educational views. It emerges that Feyerabend is best (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Feyerabend on Science and Education.Ian James Kidd - 2013 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 47 (3):407-422.
    This article offers a sympathetic interpretation of Paul Feyerabend's remarks on science and education. I present a formative episode in the development of his educational ideas—the ‘Berkeley experience'—and describe how it affected his views on the place of science within modern education. It emerges that Feyerabend arrived at a conception of education closely related to that of Michael Oakeshott and Martin Heidegger—that of education as ‘releasement’. Each of those three figures argued that the purpose of education was not to induct (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Feyerabend, Pseudo-Dionysius, and the Ineffability of Reality.Ian Kidd - 2012 - Philosophia 40 (2):365-377.
    This paper explores the influence of the fifth-century Christian Neoplatonist Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite (Denys) on the twentieth-century philosopher of science Paul Feyerabend. I argue that the later Feyerabend took from Denys a metaphysical claim—the ‘doctrine of ineffability’—intended to support epistemic pluralism. The paper has five parts. Part one introduces Denys and Feyerabend’s common epistemological concern to deny the possibility of human knowledge of ultimate reality. Part two examines Denys’ arguments for the ‘ineffability’ of God as presented in On the Divine (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Obituary of Paul K. Feyerabend (1924–1994).Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 1994 - Erkenntnis 40 (3):289 - 292.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • More letters by Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on Proto-Structure.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (4):610-632.
    The paper contains two yet unknown letters that Feyerabend wrote to Kuhn in 1960 or 1961 on a draft of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. In these letters, Feyerabend criticises both details of Kuhn's book and its general direction. The letters anticipate many of the arguments that were put forward in the public controversy against Kuhn's position, including some of the (numerous) misunderstandings. Feyerabend's assertions and arguments are very characteristic of his position in the early sixties.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Between relativism and pluralism: Philosophical and political relativism in Feyerabend's late work.Lisa Heller - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 57:96-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Nietzsche, Feyerabend, and the voices of relativism.Gordon C. F. Bearn - 1986 - Metaphilosophy 17 (2-3):135-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The paradox of meaning variance.Jerzy Giedymin - 1970 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 21 (3):257-268.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Consolations for the irrationalist?Jerzy Giedymin - 1971 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 22 (1):39-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Beyond truth and falsehood. [REVIEW]Ernest Gellner - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (4):331-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Feyerabend, truth, and relativisms: Footnotes to the Italian debate.Stefano Gattei - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 57:87-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Feyerabendian Pragmatism.Jeff Foss - 2018 - Spontaneous Generations 9 (1):26-30.
    In the not-too-distant future the scientific realism debate will be absorbed into the far more ancient-and-venerable, old-and-unqualified, realism debate. The first efficient mover of this absorption will be the fact that scientific ontology is a growing and very mixed bag, including not just rocks, plants, animals, and stars, but the Higgs boson, the Big Bang, evolutionary pressures, teenage anxieties, economic growth, social trends, countries, industrial toxins, and hedge funds. Trying to hedge off these ever-stranger newcomers by such moves as castling (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Will the Popperian Feyerabend please step forward: Pluralistic, Popperian themes in the philosophy of Paul Feyerabend.Robert P. Farrell - 2000 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14 (3):257 – 266.
    John Preston has claimed that we must understand Paul Feyerabend's later, post-1970, philosophy in terms of a disappointed Popperianism: that Feyerabend became a sceptical, relativistic, literal anarchist because of his perception of the failure of Popper's philosophy. I argue that this claim cannot be supported and trace the development of Feyerabend's philosophy in terms of a commitment to the central Popperian themes of criticism and critical explanatory progress. This commitment led Feyerabend to reject Popper's specific methodology in favour of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A problem for the eliminative materialist.Nicholas Everitt - 1981 - Mind 90 (February):428-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Brecht and Lukács as teachers of Feyerabend and Lakatos: the Feyerabend-Lakatos debate as scientific recapitulation of the Brecht- Lukács debate.Val Dusek - 1998 - History of the Human Sciences 11 (2):25-44.
    Feyerabend and Lakatos were invited to be assistants of the literary Marxists Brecht and Lukács, respectively. In the 1930s Expressionism Debate, Lukács associated artistic expressionism with irrationalism and fascism, while Brecht criticized Lukács' anti-modernism. Lakatos' criti cisms of Kuhn echo Lukács' denunciations of German idealism, and Lukács influenced the terminology and topics in Lakatos' methodol ogy. Lakatos, concerned with progress, and fearful of irrationalism and degeneration, recapitulates positions of his teacher, Lukács, in the latter's attack on modern art. Feyerabend's criticisms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Meaning and the Moral Sciences.Hilary Putnam - 1978 - Boston: Routledge.
    First published in 1978, this reissue presents a seminal philosophical work by professor Putnam, in which he puts forward a conception of knowledge which makes ethics, practical knowledge and non-mathematic parts of the social sciences just as much parts of 'knowledge' as the sciences themselves. He also rejects the idea that knowledge can be demarcated from non-knowledge by the fact that the former alone adheres to 'the scientific method'. The first part of the book consists of Professor Putnam's John Locke (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   248 citations  
  • Versuchungen Aufsätze zur Philosophie Paul Feyerabends.Hans Peter Duerr (ed.) - 1980 - Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The methodology of scientific research programmes.Imre Lakatos - 1978 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Imre Lakatos' philosophical and scientific papers are published here in two volumes. Volume I brings together his very influential but scattered papers on the philosophy of the physical sciences, and includes one important unpublished essay on the effect of Newton's scientific achievement. Volume II presents his work on the philosophy of mathematics (much of it unpublished), together with some critical essays on contemporary philosophers of science and some famous polemical writings on political and educational issues. Imre Lakatos had an influence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   405 citations  
  • The Rationality of Science.W. Newton-Smith - 1981 - Boston: Routledge.
    First published in 2002. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   197 citations  
  • Evolution and the Naked Truth: Darwinian Approach to Philosophy.Gonzalo Munevar - 2020 - Routledge.
    Published in 1998, the main aim of this book is to use a naturalistic, evolutionary approach to solve some of the most important problems in philosophy. The first two problems come from the philosophy of science: the problem of rationality of science and the problem of truth in science. In presenting the first problem, the author argues that the views of Kuhn and Feyerabend do create a very serious challenge to traditional epistemology, however, if the assumption of individual rationality is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Discourses of Science.Marcello Pera - 1994 - University of Chicago Press.
    In this much-anticipated revision and translation of Scienza e Retorica, Marcello Pera argues that rhetoric is central to the making of scientific knowledge. Pera begins with an attack of what he calls the "Cartesian syndrome"--the fixation on method common to both defenders of traditional philosophy of science and its detractors. He argues that in assuming the primacy of methodological rules, both sides get it wrong. Scientific knowledge is neither the simple mirror of nature nor a cultural construct imposed by contingent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The Semantic Conception of Theories and Scientific Realism.Frederick Suppe - 1989 - University of Illinois Press.
    Frederick Suppe has come to enjoy a position of undisputed leadership in the post-positivistic philosophy of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   213 citations  
  • Feyerabend and Scientific Values: Tightrope-walking Rationality.Robert P. Farrell - 2003 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    In this book it is argued that this picture of Feyerabend is false.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Beyond Reason: Essays on the Philosophy of Paul Feyerabend.Gonzalo Munévar (ed.) - 1991 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    Some philosophers think that Paul Feyerabend is a clown, a great many others think that he is one of the most exciting philosophers of science of this century. For me the truth does not lie somewhere in between, for I am decidedly of the second opinion, an opinion that is becoming general around the world as this century comes to an end and history begins to cast its appraising eye upon the intellectual harvest of our era. A good example of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Incommensurability Thesis.Howard Sankey - 1994 - Abingdon: Taylor and Francis.
    This book presents a critical analysis of the semantic incommensurability thesis of Thomas Kuhn and Paul Feyerabend. In putting forward the thesis of incommensurability, Kuhn and Feyerabend drew attention to complex issues concerning the phenomenon of conceptual change in science. They raised serious problems about the semantic and logical relations between the content of theories which deploy unlike systems of concepts. Yet few of the more extreme claims associated with incommensurability stand scrutiny. The argument of this book is as follows. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Rationality and relativism.Martin Hollis & Steven Lukes (eds.) - 1982 - Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
    The contributors represent the complete spectrum of positions between a relativism that challenges the very concept of a single world and the idea that there are ascertainable, objective universals.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science.Ian Hacking - 1983 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This 1983 book is a lively and clearly written introduction to the philosophy of natural science, organized around the central theme of scientific realism. It has two parts. 'Representing' deals with the different philosophical accounts of scientific objectivity and the reality of scientific entities. The views of Kuhn, Feyerabend, Lakatos, Putnam, van Fraassen, and others, are all considered. 'Intervening' presents the first sustained treatment of experimental science for many years and uses it to give a new direction to debates about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   761 citations  
  • Science, understanding, and truth: (a study of the meaning variance problem in the philosophy of science).R. D. Gunaratne - 1980 - [Colombo]: Ministry of Higher Education, Republic of Sri Lanka.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation