Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Sceptical Intuitions.Duncan Pritchard - 2014 - In Anthony Robert Booth & Darrell P. Rowbottom (eds.), Intuitions. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press UK.
    The chapter begins by exploring a philosophical case study of the use of intuitions — viz., the debate regarding the problem of radical scepticism, paying particular attention to key figures within this debate such as Barry Stroud, John Austin, and Ludwig Wittgenstein. It contends that this debate demonstrates something interesting about the nature of intuitions and the role that they can play in philosophical inquiry. In particular, the chapter argues that we need to think of the philosophical use of intuitions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Authenticity of the Ordinary.David Egan - 2013 - In David Egan Stephen Reynolds & Aaron James Wendland (eds.), Wittgenstein and Heidegger. Routledge. pp. 66-81.
    The appeal to ordinary language is a central feature of Wittgenstein’s later philosophy: he reminds us that our words find meaning in the ordinary practices and forms of life in which they are used. This emphasis on the ordinary may seem to clash with Heidegger’s claim that average everyday understanding is marked by inauthenticity: is Wittgenstein’s emphasis on ordinary language fundamentally inauthentic? On the contrary, I argue, Wittgenstein’s emphasis on the ungroundedness of our ordinary practices parallels Heidegger’s discussion of anxiety (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Disowning Knowledge: In Seven Plays of Shakespeare.Stanley Cavell - 2003 - Cambridge University Press.
    Reissued with a new preface and a new essay on Macbeth, King Lear, Othello, Coriolanius, Hamlet and The Winter's Tale, this famous collection of essays on Shakespeare's tragedies considers the plays as responses to the crisis of knowledge and the emergence of modern skepticism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Uses of Sense. [REVIEW]Rom Harré - 1992 - International Studies in Philosophy 24 (1):145-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Uses of Sense: Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Language.Marie Mcginn - 1990 - Philosophical Books 31 (2):88-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgensteinian “quietism”.John McDowell - 2009 - Common Knowledge 15 (3):365-372.
    In his Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein describes, and represents himself as pursuing, a way of doing philosophy without putting forward philosophical theses. I exemplify his approach with a sketch of his treatment of rule following. I focus in particular on the simple case of following a signpost, conceived as an expression of a rule for getting to a destination. Wittgenstein uncovers a threat that we will find it mysterious how one could learn from a signpost which way to go, and he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Stanley Cavell: Philosophy's Recounting of the Ordinary.Stephen Mulhall - 1994 - Oxford, GB: Clarendon Press.
    Stephen Mulhall presents the first full philosophical study of the work of Stanley Cavell. Cavell, a leading contemporary American thinker, is best known for his highly influential contributions to the fields of film studies, Shakespearian literary criticism, and the confluence of psychoanalysis and literary theory; Mulhall examines the broad spectrum of his thought, elucidating its essentially philosophical roots and trajectory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Virtue and Reason.John Mcdowell - 1979 - The Monist 62 (3):331-350.
    1. Presumably the point of, say, inculcating a moral outlook lies in a concern with how people live. It may seem that the very idea of a moral outlook makes room for, and requires, the existence of moral theory, conceived as a discipline which seeks to formulate acceptable principles of conduct. It is then natural to think of ethics as a branch of philosophy related to moral theory, so conceived, rather as the philosophy of science is related to science. On (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   580 citations  
  • Thought’s Footing. [REVIEW]Tamara Dobler - 2008 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 8 (3):389-393.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Moore and Wittgenstein: scepticism, certainty, and common sense.Annalisa Coliva - 2010 - New York, NY: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Does scepticism threaten our common sense picture of the world? Does it really undermine our deep-rooted certainties? Answers to these questions are offered through a comparative study of the epistemological work of two key figures in the history of analytic philosophy, G. E. Moore and Ludwig Wittgenstein.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • A defence of common sense.George Edward Moore - 1925 - In J. H. Muirhead (ed.), Contemporary British Philosophy, Second Series. George Allen and Unwin.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • The true and the false: the domain of the pragmatic.Charles Travis - 1981 - Amsterdam: Benjamins.
    The main thrust of the present work is to show why truth and truth bearers lie essentially beyond the descriptive reach of semantics, and to outline a theory of ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Thought's footing: a theme in Wittgenstein's philosophical investigations.Charles Travis - 2006 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Thought's Footing is an enquiry into the relationship between the ways things are and the way we think and talk about them. It is also a study of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations: Charles Travis develops his account of certain key themes into a unified view of the work as a whole. The central question is: how does thought get its footing? How can the thought that things are a certain way be connected to things being that way?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Other Minds.J. L. Austin - 2000 - In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: readings in contemporary epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   209 citations  
  • Understanding Wittgenstein's On certainty.Danièle Moyal-Sharrock - 2004 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    This radical reading of Wittgenstein's third and last masterpiece, On Certainty, has major implications for philosophy. It elucidates Wittgenstein's ultimate thoughts on the nature of our basic beliefs and his demystification of scepticism. Our basic certainties are shown to be nonepistemic, nonpropositional attitudes that, as such, have no verbal occurrence but manifest themselves exclusively in our actions. This fundamental certainty is a belief-in, a primitive confidence or ur-trust whose practical nature bridges the hitherto unresolved categorial gap between belief and action.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • Unnatural doubts: epistemological realism and the basis of scepticism.Michael Williams - 1991 - Cambridge, USA: Blackwell.
    In Unnatural Doubts, Michael Williams constructs a masterly polemic against the very idea of epistemology, as traditionally conceived.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   146 citations  
  • Sense and certainty: a dissolution of scepticism.Marie McGinn - 1989 - New York, NY, USA: Blackwell.
    This dissertation aims to construct a non-dogmatic defence of common sense. It tries to show why the absence of justification for the judgements of common sense, which the sceptic reveals, does not invalidate them.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • The significance of philosophical scepticism.Barry Stroud - 1984 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   326 citations  
  • The possibility of knowledge.Quassim Cassam - 2007 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 74 (1):125-141.
    I focus on two questions: what is knowledge, and how is knowledge possible? The latter is an example of a how-possible question. I argue that how-possible questions are obstacle-dependent and that they need to be dealt with at three different levels, the level of means, of obstacle-removal, and of enabling conditions. At the first of these levels the possibility of knowledge is accounted for by identifying means of knowing, and I argue that the identification of such means also contributes to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on meaning and use.James Conant - 1998 - Philosophical Investigations 21 (3):222–250.
    Wittgenstein is usually taken to have held that the use of a term is not mentally constrained. That is utterly wrong. A use of language unconstrained by meaning is attributed by him to "meaning-blind" or "aspect-blind" creatures, not to us. We observe meaning when an aspect dawns on us; meaning is the impression (Eindruck) of a term as fitting something; hence, unlike pain, it cannot stand alone. That is a mentalistic theory of meaning: use is determined by images (Vorstellungen) that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Defending common sense.Norman Malcolm - 1949 - Philosophical Review 58 (3):201-220.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Hitchcock and Cavell.Richard Allen - 2006 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (1):43–53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Alief and Belief.Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2008 - Journal of Philosophy 105 (10):634-663.
    Forthcoming, Journal of Philosophy [pdf manuscript].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   378 citations  
  • Knowledge and the internal.John McDowell - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4):877-93.
    1. I am going to work with an idea from Sellars, that knowledge—at least as enjoyed by rational animals—is a certain sort of standing in the space of reasons. My concern is a familiar philosophical dialectic, which I shall approach in terms of what happens to the Sellarsian idea when the image of standings in the space of reasons undergoes a certain deformation. That it is a deformation is something we can learn from how unsatisfactory the familiar dialectic is.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   192 citations  
  • Knowledge and the Internal.John McDowell - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4):877-893.
    1. I am going to work with an idea from Sellars, that knowledge—at least as enjoyed by rational animals—is a certain sort of standing in the space of reasons. My concern is a familiar philosophical dialectic, which I shall approach in terms of what happens to the Sellarsian idea when the image of standings in the space of reasons undergoes a certain deformation. That it is a deformation is something we can learn from how unsatisfactory the familiar dialectic is.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • Must we mean what we say?Stanley Cavell - 1964 - In Vere Claiborne Chappell (ed.), Ordinary language: essays in philosophical method. New York: Dover Publications. pp. 172 – 212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  • Skepticism, Metaphors and Vertigo.Rico Gutschmidt - 2016 - Wittgenstein-Studien 7 (1):131-147.
    The relation of Wittgenstein’s later philosophy to skepticism seems to be ambiguous, since he rejects radical skepticism but also highlights the groundlessness of our beliefs. In this paper, I am going to discuss Wittgenstein’s hinge propositions in this respect. Against the usual view, I will show that they do not function as a contextualist or foundationalist refutation of skepticism. What is more, they also do not confirm skepticism. In contrast, I will argue that following Wittgenstein skepticism is neither false nor (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Legacy of Skepticism.Thompson Clarke - 1972 - Journal of Philosophy 69 (20):754.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Alief and belief.Tamar Gendler - 2019 - In Jeremy Fantl, Matthew McGrath & Ernest Sosa (eds.), Contemporary epistemology: an anthology. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Virtue and Reason.John McDowell - 1997 - In Roger Crisp & Michael Slote (eds.), Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   334 citations  
  • The Possibility of Knowledge.Quassim Cassam (ed.) - 2007 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    How is knowledge of the external world possible? How is knowledge of other minds possible? How is a priori knowledge possible? These are all examples of how-possible questions in epistemology. In this highly original book Quassim Cassam explains how such questions arise and how they should be answered.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • The Illusion of Doubt.Genia Schönbaumsfeld - 2016 - Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press UK.
    The Illusion of Doubt confronts one of the most important questions in philosophy and beyond: what can we know? The radical sceptic's answer is 'not very much' if we cannot prove that we are not subject to deception. For centuries philosophers have been impressed by the radical sceptic's move, but this book shows that the radical sceptical problem turns out to be an illusion created by a mistaken picture of our evidential situation. This means that we don't need to answer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Unnatural Doubts: Epistemological Realism and the Basis of Scepticism.Michael Williams - 1993 - Philosophy 68 (263):110-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations