Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Behind the Geometrical Method: A Reading of Spinoza's Ethics.Edwin Curley - 1988 - Princeton University Press.
    This book is the fruit of twenty-five years of study of Spinoza by the editor and translator of a new and widely acclaimed edition of Spinoza's collected works. Based on three lectures delivered at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem in 1984, the work provides a useful focal point for continued discussion of the relationship between Descartes and Spinoza, while also serving as a readable and relatively brief but substantial introduction to the Ethics for students. Behind the Geometrical Method is actually (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Spinoza On Eternal Life.Clare Carlisle - 2015 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 89 (1):69-96.
    This article argues that Spinoza’s account of the eternity of the mind in Part V of the Ethics offers a re-interpretation of the Christian doctrine of eternal life. While Spinoza rejects the orthodox Christian teaching belief in personal immortality and the resurrection of the body, he presents an alternative account of human eternity that retains certain key characteristics of the Johannine doctrine of eternal life, especially as this is articulated in the First Letter of John. The article shows how Spinoza’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Spinoza's distinction between rational and intuitive knowledge.Spencer Carr - 1978 - Philosophical Review 87 (2):241-252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Spinoza's Acquiescentia.Clare Carlisle - 2017 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 55 (2):209-236.
    Spinoza's account of acquiescentia has been obscured by inconsistent translations of acquiescentia, and forms of the verb acquiescere, in the standard English edition of the Ethics. For Spinoza, acquiescentia is an inherently cognitive affect, since it involves an idea of oneself (as the cause of one's joy). As such, the affect is closely correlated to the three kinds of cognition identified by Spinoza in Ethics II. Just as there are three kinds of cognition, so too are there three kinds of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Descartes (and Spinoza) on Intellectual Experience and Skepticism.John Carriero - 2020 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 68 (2):21-42.
    Kartezjusz w kwestii intelektualnego doświadczenia i sceptycyzmu Epistemologia Kartezjusza jest zakorzeniona w jego głębokim zainteresowaniu i uznaniu dla tego, co można by nazwać intelektualnym doświadczeniem, lub dokładniej przejrzystym intelektualnym doświadczeniem. To zainteresowanie intelektualnym doświadczeniem, jak mi się wydaje, podzielali inni racjonaliści, Spinoza i Leibniz. W części pierwszej artykułu staram się ulokować fenomen przejrzystego intelektualnego doświadczenia w ramach doktryny Kartezjusza i Spinozy. Usiłuję pokazać, że jeśli nie uwzględnimy w sposób właściwy charakteru tego doświadczenia, to ryzykujemy utratą wglądu w centralne motywy leżące (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Five Types of Ethical Theory.C. D. Broad - 1930 - Mind 39 (155):338-346.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Five Types of Ethical Theory.C. D. Broad - 1930 - Humana Mente 5 (19):463-465.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  • Love and Objective Reality in Spinoza’s Account of the Mind’s Power over the Affects.Lilli Alanen - 2023 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 101 (3):517-533.
    This paper explores Spinoza’s therapy of passions and method of salvation through knowledge and love of God. His optimism about this method is perplexing: it is not even clear how his God, who is unlike any traditional notion of divinity, can be loved. Sorting out Spinoza’s view involves distinguishing an ethics of bondage from another of freedom, and two corresponding notions of love of God. The paper argues that the highest kind of love—‘pure intellectual love of God’—should not be understood (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Spinoza on Causa Sui.Yitzhak Y. Melamed - 2021 - In A Companion to Spinoza. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. pp. 116–125.
    For many of Spinoza's contemporaries and predecessors the very notion of causa sui was utterly absurd, akin to a Baron Munchausen attempting to lift himself above a river by pulling his hair up. This chapter examines Descartes’ engagement with the notion of causa sui, and shows that Spinoza understood the causation of causa sui as efficient, and not formal, causation. Proving the existence of God was the stated aim of Descartes’ Third Meditation. Descartes’ response to Caterus is pretty simple: he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reflective Knowledge.Kristin Primus - 2021 - In Yitzhak Y. Melamed (ed.), A Companion to Spinoza. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. pp. 265–275.
    This chapter describes Spinoza's obscure “ideas of ideas” doctrine and his claim that “as soon as one knows something, one knows that one knows it, and simultaneously knows that one knows that one knows, and so on, to infinity”. Spinoza holds that the human mind is a representation of the body: the “objectum of the idea constituting the human mind” is the human body. Suppose ideas are essentially self‐reflexive, and that this reflexive awareness, the “idea of the idea,” makes the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Spinoza on Human and Divine Knowledge.Ursula Renz & Barnaby R. Hutchins - 2021 - In Yitzhak Y. Melamed (ed.), A Companion to Spinoza. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. pp. 251–264.
    This chapter argues that the human perspective is not fully reducible – that is, that something would indeed be lost in the absence of the human perspective. It shows that epistemic subjectivity itself is an irreducible, ineliminable feature of the human standpoint. Subjectivity goes along with substantiality, and to be an epistemic subject is to be a substance with a mind. In E2p13, Spinoza identifies the mind's object with the body, thereby specifying where the multiplicity of epistemic subjects comes from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Necessity and Nature in Spinoza's Philosophy.Don Garrett - 2018 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Mind's Eternity in Spinoza's Ethics.Steven Parchment - 2000 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (3):349-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Spinoza's Theory of the Eternity of the Mind.Diane Steinberg - 1981 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 (1):35 - 68.
    In part I of this paper I argue that on his theory of the mind as the idea of an actually existing body Spinoza is unable to account for the ability of the mind to have adequate knowledge, and I suggest that his theory of the eternity of the mind can be viewed as his solution to this problem. In part II I deal with the question of the meaning of ‘eternity’ in Spinoza, in regard both to God and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Distinction between Reason and Intuitive Knowledge in Spinoza's Ethics.Sanem Soyarslan - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 24 (1):27-54.
    While both intuitive knowledge and reason are adequate ways of knowing for Spinoza, they are not equal. Intuitive knowledge, which Spinoza describes as the ‘greatest virtue of mind’, is superior to reason. The nature of this superiority has been the subject of some controversy due to Spinoza's notoriously parsimonious treatment of the distinction between reason and intuitive knowledge in the Ethics. In this paper, I argue that intuitive knowledge differs from reason not only in terms of its method of cognition—but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Descartes’s Argument for the Existence of the Idea of an Infinite Being.Anat Schechtman - 2014 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 52 (3):487-517.
    the meditations on first philosophy presents us with an alleged proof for the existence of God that proceeds from the existence of an idea of an infinite being in the human mind—an idea of God—to the existence of God himself. Insofar as we have an idea of an infinite being, an idea with “infinite objective reality,” we can legitimately ask whence it came to us. The only possible cause of this idea, claims Descartes, is an infinite being, namely, God. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Salvation as a state of mind: The place of acquiescentia in Spinoza's ethics.Donald Rutherford - 1999 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 7 (3):447 – 473.
    (1999). Salvation as a state of mind: The place of acquiescentia in spinoza's ethics. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 7, No. 3, pp. 447-473. doi: 10.1080/09608789908571039.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Part of Nature: Self-Knowledge In Spinoza’s Ethics.Michael Della Rocca & Genevieve Lloyd - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (1):116.
    Writing to Henry Oldenburg in 1665, Spinoza says that he regards the human body as a part of nature. “But,” he adds significantly, “as far as the human mind is concerned, I think it is a part of nature too.” Genevieve Lloyd’s elegantly written book aims to investigate the meaning, implications and attractions of these characteristic Spinozistic claims.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Spinoza’s Monism I: Ruling Out Eternal-Durational Causation.Kristin Primus - 2023 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 105 (2):265-288.
    In this essay, I suggest that Spinoza acknowledges a distinction between formal reality that is infinite and timelessly eternal and formal reality that is non-infinite (i. e., finite or indefinite) and non-eternal (i. e., enduring). I also argue that if, in Spinoza’s system, only intelligible causation is genuine causation, then infinite, timelessly eternal formal reality cannot cause non-infinite, non-eternal formal reality. A denial of eternal-durational causation generates a puzzle, however: if no enduring thing – not even the sempiternal, indefinite individual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Spinoza’s Monism II: A Proposal.Kristin Primus - 2023 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 105 (3):444-469.
    An old question in Spinoza scholarship is how finite, non-eternal things transitively caused by other finite, non-eternal things (i. e., the entities described in propositions like E1p28) are caused by the infinite, eternal substance, given that what follows either directly or indirectly from the divine nature is infinite and eternal (E1p21–23). In “Spinoza’s Monism I,” “Spinoza’s Monism I,” in the previous issue of this journal. I pointed out that most commentators answer this question by invoking entities that are indefinite and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Spinoza’s ‘Infinite Modes’ Reconsidered.Kristin Primus - 2019 - Journal of Modern Philosophy 1 (1):1-29.
    My two principal aims in this essay are interconnected. One aim is to provide a new interpretation of the ‘infinite modes’ in Spinoza’s Ethics. I argue that for Spinoza, God, conceived as the one infinite and eternal substance, is not to be understood as causing two kinds of modes, some infinite and eternal and the rest finite and non-eternal. That there cannot be such a bifurcation of divine effects is what I take the ‘infinite mode’ propositions, E1p21–23, to establish; E1p21–23 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Spinoza on Destroying Passions with Reason.Colin Marshall - 2012 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (1):139-160.
    Spinoza claims we can control any passion by forming a more clear and distinct idea of it. The interpretive consensus is that Spinoza is either wrong or over-stating his view. I argue that Spinoza’s view is plausible and insightful. After breaking down Spinoza’s characterization of the relevant act, I consider four existing interpretations and conclude that each is unsatisfactory. I then consider a further problem for Spinoza: how his definitions of ‘action’ and ‘passion’ make room for passions becoming action. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Spinozas metaphysics of desire.L. In Martin - 2004 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 86 (1):21-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Infinite Understanding, Scientia Intuitiva, and Ethics 1.16.Margaret D. Wilson - 1983 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 8 (1):181-191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Part of nature: self-knowledge in Spinoza's Ethics.Genevieve Lloyd - 1994 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    Spinoza's doctrine of the uniqueness of substance has been interpreted as absorbing individual self-consciousness into an all-embracing whole.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Spinozas Metaphysics of Desire.Martin Lin - 2004 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 86 (1):21-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Change and the eternal part of the mind in Spinoza.Michael Lebuffe - 2010 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 91 (3):369-384.
    Spinoza insists that we can during the course of our lives increase that part of the mind that is constituted by knowledge, but he also calls that part of the mind its eternal part. How can what is eternal increase? I defend an interpretation on which there is a sense in which the eternal part of the mind can become greater without changing intrinsically at all.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Major Trends in Jewish Mysticism. [REVIEW]P. O. K. & Gershom G. Scholem - 1943 - Journal of Philosophy 40 (17):474.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Spinoza on Composition, Causation, and the Mind's Eternity.John Grey - 2014 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (3):446-467.
    Spinoza's doctrine of the eternity of the mind is often understood as the claim that the mind has a part that is eternal. I appeal to two principles that Spinoza takes to govern parthood and causation to raise a new problem for this reading. Spinoza takes the composition of one thing from many to require causal interaction among the many. Yet he also holds that eternal things cannot causally interact, without mediation, with things in duration. So the human mind, since (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A Study of Spinoza's Ethics.Jonathan Bennett - 1984 - Critica 16 (48):110-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   173 citations  
  • The power of reason in Spinoza.Martin Lin - 2009 - In Olli Koistinen (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza's Ethics. Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Spinoza on the Essence of the Human Body and the Part of the Mind that is Eternal.Don Garrett - 2009 - In Olli Koistinen (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza's Ethics. Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Spinoza's proof of immortality.Alan Donagan - 1973 - In Spinoza: A Collection of Critical Essays. pp. 241--58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Spinoza on Intentionality, Materialism, and Mind-Body Relations.Karolina Hübner - 2019 - Philosophers' Imprint 19.
    The paper examines a relatively neglected element of Spinoza's theory of mind-body relations: the intentional relation between human minds and bodies, which for Spinoza constitutes their “union”. Prima facie textual evidence suggests, and many readers agree, that because for Spinoza human minds are essentially ideas of bodies, Spinoza is also committed to an ontological and explanatory dependence of certain properties of human minds on properties of bodies, and thus to a version of materialism. The paper argues that such dependence would (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Spinoza's Social Sage: Emotion and the Power of Reason in Spinoza’s Social Theory.Ericka Tucker - 2015 - Revista Conatus 9 (17):23-41.
    Far from his ‘rationalist’ image, Spinoza recognizes that we do not emerge from the ground as fully formed rational agents. We are born and develop in social worlds, where our affects, values and conceptions of the world are formed. For Spinoza, even the ‘free’ individual or sage is affected by the social and emotional worlds in which he argues they ought to live. Yet, Spinoza is ambivalent about the social emotions. These socially conditioned affects and values may be harmful to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • L'amour intellectuel de dieu, partie éternelle de l'«amor erga deum».Alexandre Matheron - forthcoming - Les Etudes Philosophiques.
    L'amor erga Deum étudié dans la proposition 15 d'Éthique V et l'amour intellectuel de Dieu étudié dans les propositions 32-33 sont en réalité un seul et même amour. Mais, dans le premier cas, cet amour est considéré globalement, sous tous ses aspects, y compris chronologiques; dans le second, au contraire, il est considéré dans sa seule nature, abstraction faite de ses aspects événementiels, et cette réduction met en lumière le petit noyau d'autonomie absolue qui constitue ce qu'il y a en (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Major Trends in Jewish Mysticism.Gershom G. Scholem - 1946 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 19 (1):138-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Major Trends in Jewish Mysticism.Gershom G. Scholem - 1946 - Philosophy 23 (85):188-189.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • From Ordinary Life to Blessedness, The Power of Intuitive Knowledge in Spinoza's Ethics.Sanem Soyarslan - 2014 - In Matthew Kisner & Andrew Youpa (eds.), Essays on Spinoza's Ethical Theory. New York, USA: Oxford University Press. pp. 236-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • La stratégie du conatus. Affirmation et résistance chez Spinoza.Laurent Bove - 1997 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 59 (4):758-758.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Descartes and Spinoza on Persistance and Conatus.Daniel Garber - 1994 - Studia Spinozana: An International and Interdisciplinary Series 10:43-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Remarques sur l'immortalité de l''me chez Spinoza.Alexandre Matheron - 1972 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 3:369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation