Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Aristotle's theology.Stephen Menn - 2012 - In Christopher Shields (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 422.
    When Aristotle speaks of theologikê, he means not the study of a single God, but the study of gods and divine things in general. He never uses the phrase “the unmoved mover” to pick out just one being, and that phrase would not express the essence of the beings it applies to. To see what sort of religious interest there might be in such a being, and how the words “god” and “divine” enter into Aristotle's philosophy, it is best to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Noῦs and Nature in De Anima III.Sarah Broadie - 1996 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 12 (1):163-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle on Form, Substance, and Universals: A Dilemma.James H. Lesher - 1971 - Phronesis 16 (1):169-178.
    In book Zeta of the Metaphysics and elsewhere Aristotle appears to commit himself to the following propositions: (1) No universal can be substance; (2) Form is a universal; and (3) Form is that which is most truly substance. These propositions appear to constitute an inconsistent triad lying at the heart of Aristotle’s ontology. A number of attempts have been made to rescue Aristotle from the charge of inconsistency. Some have claimed that Aristotle did not subscribe to (1), but only to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Aristotle's Two Intellects: A Modest Proposal.Victor Caston - 1999 - Phronesis 44 (3):199-227.
    In "De anima" 3.5, Aristotle argues for the existence of a second intellect, the so-called "Agent Intellect." The logical structure of his argument turns on a distinction between different types of soul, rather than different faculties within a given soul; and the attributes he assigns to the second species make it clear that his concern here -- as at the climax of his other great works, such as the "Metaphysics," the "Nicomachean" and the "Eudemian Ethics" -- is the difference between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Aristotle on consciousness.Victor Caston - 2002 - Mind 111 (444):751-815.
    Aristotle's discussion of perceiving that we perceive has points of contact with two contemporary debates about consciousness: the first over whether consciousness is an intrinsic feature of mental states or a higher-order thought or perception; the second concerning the qualitative nature of experience. In both cases, Aristotle's views cut down the middle of an apparent dichotomy, in a way that does justice to each set of intuitions, while avoiding their attendant difficulties. With regard to the first issue?the primary focus of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Traditional Religion and Its Natural Function in Aristotle.Mor Segev - 2018 - Classical World: A Quarterly Journal on Antiquity 111 (3):295-320.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle on Natural Slavery.Malcolm Heath - 2008 - Phronesis 53 (3):243-270.
    Aristotle's claim that natural slaves do not possess autonomous rationality (Pol. 1.5, 1254b20-23) cannot plausibly be interpreted in an unrestricted sense, since this would conflict with what Aristotle knew about non-Greek societies. Aristotle's argument requires only a lack of autonomous practical rationality. An impairment of the capacity for integrated practical deliberation, resulting from an environmentally induced excess or deficiency in thumos (Pol. 7.7, 1327b18-31), would be sufficient to make natural slaves incapable of eudaimonia without being obtrusively implausible relative to what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The Place of Mankind in Aristotle’s Zoology.James G. Lennox - 1999 - Philosophical Topics 27 (1):1-16.
    Historians of psychology often treat Aristotle’s De Anima as the first scientific treatment of their subject; and historians of biology do likewise with his zoological treatises. How are the investigations recorded in works such as the Parts of Animals and History of Animals connected to those in the De Anima? More specifically, given Aristotle’s views about man’s special and distinctive cognitive capacities, what does he think about man as an object of a distinctively zoological investigation? In the following pages, this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Unity of Intellect in Aristotle's De Anima.Lloyd Gerson - 2004 - Phronesis 49 (4):348-373.
    Desperately difficult texts inevitably elicit desperate hermeneutical measures. Aristotle's De Anima, book three, chapter five, is evidently one such text. At least since the time of Alexander of Aphrodisias, scholars have felt compelled to draw some remarkable conclusions regarding Aristotle's brief remarks in this passage regarding intellect. One such claim is that in chapter five, Aristotle introduces a second intellect, the so-called 'agent intellect', an intellect distinct from the 'passive intellect', the supposed focus of discussion up until this passage.1 This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle on the Separability of Mind.Fred D. Miller - 2012 - In Christopher Shields (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 306-339.
    Discusses the sense of separability in Aristotle and how they apply to the separability of mind or nous.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Relation of the Intellect to the Body: Commentary on Broadie.Victor Caston - 1996 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 12 (1):177-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle's "Nicomachean Ethics".Gabriel Richardson Lear - 2005 - Princeton University Press.
    Gabriel Richardson Lear presents a bold new approach to one of the enduring debates about Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics: the controversy about whether it coherently argues that the best life for humans is one devoted to a single activity, namely philosophical contemplation. Many scholars oppose this reading because the bulk of the Ethics is devoted to various moral virtues--courage and generosity, for example--that are not in any obvious way either manifestations of philosophical contemplation or subordinated to it. They argue that Aristotle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • The private parts of animals: Aristotle on the teleology of sexual difference.Karen Nielsen - 2008 - Phronesis 53 (4-5):373-405.
    In this paper I examine Aristotle's account of sexual difference in Generation of Animals, arguing that Aristotle conceives of the production of males as the result of a successful teleological process, while he sees the production of females as due to material forces that defeat the norms of nature. My suggestion is that Aristotle endorses what I call the "degrees of perfection" model. I challenge Devin Henry's attempt to argue that Aristotle explains sex determination exclusively with reference to material necessity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Slaves, Women, and Aristotle’s Natural Teleology.Joseph Karbowski - 2012 - Ancient Philosophy 32 (2):323-350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • ‘Obviously all this Agrees with my Will and my Intellect’: Schopenhauer on Active and PassiveNousin Aristotle'sDe Animaiii.5.Mor Segev - 2014 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (3):535-556.
    In one of the unpublished parts of his manuscript titled the Spicilegia, Arthur Schopenhauer presents an uncharacteristically sympathetic reading of an Aristotelian text. The text in question, De anima III. 5, happens to include the only occurrence of arguably the most controversial idea in Aristotle, namely the distinction between active and passive nous. Schopenhauer interprets these two notions as corresponding to his own notions of the ?will? and the ?intellect? or ?subject of knowledge?, respectively. The result is a unique interpretation, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle's Nous and the Modern Mind.John Sisko - 2000 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 16 (1):177-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Human Nature and Intellectualism in Aristotle.Jennifer Whiting - 1986 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 68 (1):70-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Contemplation and happiness: A reconsideration.John M. Cooper - 1987 - Synthese 72 (2):187 - 216.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle on the Separability of Mind.Fred D. Miller - 2012 - In Christopher Shields (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press USA.
    In De Anima, Aristotle addresses the problem of whether the mind is separable from the body. In book I, he broaches the broader question of whether the affections of the soul, including emotion, desire, and perception, are separable from the body. In book II, Aristotle follows his explication of the general definition of the soul with the remark that “neither the soul nor certain parts of it, if it naturally has parts, are separable from the body. Yet nothing prevents some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle on Methodological Approaches to the Study of the Human Soul.Hynek Bartoš - 2012 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 12 (2):199-220.
    This paper focuses on Aristotle’s methodology of science and its application to the study of the human soul. My aim is to contrast two significantly different methodological approaches and to formulate two pairs of premises that Aristotle employs in two clearly differentiated and independent fields of study, namely in his zoological works and in the works of practical philosophy. Acknowledging these principles, as I suggest, may shed a new light on the methodological difficulties that Aristotle indicates in the introductory chapters (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle: The Nicomachean Ethics. A commentary by the late H. H. JOACHIM. By Charles Wegener.H. H. Joachim & D. A. Rees - 1951 - Ethics 62 (4):300-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle on Thinking.Charles H. Ahn - 1992 - In Martha C. Nussbaum & Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle's de Anima. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    This essay discusses Aristotle’s theory of the intellect, which is often neglected or misunderstood. It focuses on two doctrines in the theory of intellect: Doctrine One claims that nous is essentially incorporeal and has no bodily organ; and Doctrine Two is the thesis that the intellect in act is identical with its intelligible object. It is argued that D1 is incompatible with the general definition of psuchē, and that the appearance of conflict between D1 and the need for phantasms can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Colloquium 6.John Sisko - 2000 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 16 (1):177-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations