Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Death in socrates, Plato, and Aristotle.Gareth B. Matthews - 2013 - In Fred Feldman Ben Bradley (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death. Oxford University Press. pp. 186.
    This chapter examines the views of death by ancient Greek philosophers including Aristotle, Socrates, and Plato. It suggests that Aristotle offered no cheerful optimism similar to Socrates in his “Apology” and did not provide any arguments about the immortality of the soul like Plato in “Phaedo.” What Aristotle attempted to do was to help us face immortality that can enhance our chances of living worthy lives.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Magnanimity, Mεγαλοψυχία, and the System of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.Eckart Schütrumpf - 1989 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 71 (1):10-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Camus and Nihilism.Ashley Woodward - 2011 - Sophia 50 (4):543-559.
    Camus published an essay entitled ‘Nietzsche and Nihilism,’ which was later incorporated into The Rebel . Camus' aim was to assess Nietzsche's response to the problem of nihilism. My aim is to do the same with Camus. The paper explores Camus' engagement with nihilism through its two major modalities: with respect to the individual and the question of suicide in The Myth of Sisyphus , and with respect to the collective and the question of murder in The Rebel . While (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Forms of Friendship.John M. Cooper - 1977 - Review of Metaphysics 30 (4):619 - 648.
    NEITHER in the scholarly nor in the philosophical literature on Aristotle does his account of friendship occupy a very prominent place. I suppose this is partly, though certainly not wholly, to be explained by the fact that the modern ethical theories with which Aristotle’s might demand comparison hardly make room for the discussion of any parallel phenomenon. Whatever else friendship is, it is, at least typically, a personal relationship freely, even spontaneously, entered into, and ethics, as modern theorists tend to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Empedocles' Cosmic Cycle.D. OʼBrien - 1980 - Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 36 (2):218-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Schopenhauer's pessimism and the unconditioned good.Mark Migotti - 1995 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (4):643.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Schopenhauer's Pessimism and the Unconditioned Good MARK MIGOTTI SCHOPENHAUERTOOK PESSIMISMtO be a profound doctrine that had long been accepted by the majority of humanity, albeit usually in the allegorical form given to it by one or another religious creed. Accordingly, he credited himself, not with the discovery of pessimism, but with the provision of a satisfactory philosophical exposition and defense of its claims. It was, he contended, only within (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • 5. The Makropulos Case: Reflections on the Tedium of Immortality.Bernard Williams - 1993 - In John Martin Fischer (ed.), The Metaphysics of death. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press. pp. 71-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Aristotle on intra- and inter-species friendships.Thornton Lockwood - forthcoming - In Sophia Connell (ed.), Philosophical Essays on Aristotle’s Historia Animalium.
    Although there is much scholarship on Aristotle’s account of friendship (φιλία), almost all of it has focused on inter-personal relationships between human animals. Nonetheless, in both Aristotle’s ethical and zoological writings, he documents the intra- and inter-species friendship between many kinds of animals, including between human and non-human animals. Such non-human animal friendships establish both an indirect basis for establishing moral ties between humans and non-human animals (insofar as we respect their capacity to love and befriend others) and a direct (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nietzsche's Ethics.Thomas Stern - 2019 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    This Element explains Nietzsche's ethics in his late works, from 1886 onwards. The first three sections explain the basics of his ethical theory – its context and presuppositions, its scope and its central tension. The next three sections explore Nietzsche's goals in writing a history of Christian morality, the content of that history, and whether he achieves his goals. The last two sections take a broader look, respectively, at Nietzsche's wider philosophy in light of his ethics and at the prospects (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The endoxon Mystique: What endoxa are and What They are Not.Dorothea Frede - 1885 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 43:185-215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • 5. Spinoza in the Garden of Good and Evil.Steven M. Nadler - 2001 - In Michael J. Latzer & Elmar J. Kremer (eds.), The Problem of Evil in Early Modern Philosophy. University of Toronto Press. pp. 66-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Teleological Significance of Dreaming in Aristotle.Mor Segev - 2012 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 43:107-141.
    In his discussions of dreaming in the Parva Naturalia, Aristotle neither claims nor denies that dreams serve a natural purpose. Modern scholarship generally interprets dreaming as useless and teleologically irrelevant for him. I argue that Aristotle's teleology permits certain types of dream to have a natural role in end-directed processes. Dreams are left-overs from waking experience, but they may, like certain bodily residues, be used by nature, which does ‘nothing in vain’ and makes use of available resources, for the benefit (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Is Aristotle's teleology anthropocentric?David Sedley - 1991 - Phronesis 36 (2):179-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Aristotle on greatness of soul.Roger Crisp - 2006 - In Richard Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 158--178.
    The prelims comprise: Greatness of Soul as a Virtue Greatness of Soul and other Virtues The Great‐souled Person: The “Portrait” and its Problems The Aesthetics of Virtue Acknowledgment References Further reading.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Maimonides' moral theory.David Shatz - 2005 - In Kenneth Seeskin (ed.), The Cambridge companion to Maimonides. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • January 8, 2008 political community and the highest good.John Cooper - manuscript
    The Nicomachean Ethics announces itself as a treatise on the highest human good, the “end” (t°low) of human life—eÈdaiµon€a or happiness. In the last chapter of the work (X 9) Aristotle makes it clear that the study of the happy lives of contemplation and political leadership, the virtues, friendship, and pleasure that has by then been carried out in investigating that good—these are the leading themes of the Ethics that he mentions there (1179a33-35)— leaves the treatise’s objectives not yet completely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Alexander of Aphrodisias on Divine Providence: Two Problems.R. W. Sharples - 1982 - Classical Quarterly 32 (1):198-211.
    The position on the question of divine providence of the Aristotelian commentator Alexander of Aphrodisias (fl. c. A.D. 200) is of particular interest. It marks an attempt to find avia mediabetween the Epicurean denial of any divine concern for the world, on the one hand, and the Stoic view that divine providence governs it in every detail, on the other.2As an expression of such a middle course it finds a place in later classifications of views concerning providence.3It is also of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Historical Roots of Our Ecologic Crisis.L. White & Jr - 1967 - Science 155 (3767):1203-1207.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   210 citations  
  • A Cock for Asclepius.Glenn W. Most - 1993 - Classical Quarterly 43 (01):96-.
    In any list of famous last words, Socrates' are likely to figure near the top. Details of the final moments of celebrities tend anyway to exert a peculiar fascination upon the rest of us: life's very contingency provokes a need to see lives nevertheless as meaningful organic wholes, defined as such precisely by their final closure; so that even the most trivial aspects of their ending can come to seem bearers of profound significance, soliciting moral reflections apparently not less urgent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Paradox of Fatalism and Self-Creation in Nietzsche.Brian Leiter - 2001 - In John Richardson & Brian Leiter (eds.), Nietzsche. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Aristotle's Politics: Living Well and Living Together.F. Miller - 2014 - Philosophical Quarterly 64 (254):195-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Human Nature and Intellectualism in Aristotle.Jennifer Whiting - 1986 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 68 (1):70-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • XXIV. Der Dualismus des Empedokles.W. Nestle - 1906 - Philologus: Zeitschrift für Antike Literatur Und Ihre Rezeption 65 (1-4):545-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Aristotelian Philosophy of Biology: Form, Function and Development.James G. Lennox - 2007 - Acta Philosophica 26 (1):33-52.
    In metaphysics and philosophy of science, a significant movement is making inroads, under the banner of ‘neo-Aristotelianism’. This movement has so far been focused primarily on the physical sciences; but given that Aristotle the natural scientist was above all a biologist, it is worth asking what a neo-Aristotelian philosophy of biology would look like? In this paper, I begin a discussion on precisely that question. One interesting result is that the fact that biology is now permeated by evolutionary ways of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Unconscious Emotions: A Reply to Professor Mullane.Michael Fox - 1976 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36 (3):412.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Essays on Freedom of the Will.A. Schopenhauer - 1969 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    Schopenhauer's prize essay On the Freedom of Will is one of the classics of Western philosophy, dealing with the question of free will versus determinism. His treatment of the problem of free will is by no means obsolete, containing penetrating reflections relevant to contemporary discussion. The argument of the essay is clearly and rigorously presented, and reveals many basic features of Schopenhauer's thought. As such, it forms a useful introduction to Schopenhauer's philosophy in general. Equally, the essay can be studied (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The argument for the sphericity of the universe inaristotle's de caelo: Astronomy and physics.Pierre Pellegrin - 2009 - In Alan Bowen & Christian Wildberg (eds.), New Perspectives on Aristotle’s De Caelo. Brill. pp. 117--163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle on posthumous fortune.Dominic Scott - 2000 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 18:211-29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Some Conceptual Difficulties in Aristotle’s De caelo I.9.Karel Thein - 2013 - Rhizomata 1 (1):63-84.
    : The article discusses two issues implied by the structure of De caelo I.9: Aristotle’s further defence of the uniqueness of the universe and, in more detail, the general question of whether the cosmology of De caelo overlaps, or is even compatible, with Aristotle’s theology including the notion of the Prime Mover. It offers an analysis of several long-standing difficulties including the question of whether the lines 279a18–22 imply an external mover of the heavens. The negative answer that I will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Spinoza’s Spiders, Schopenhauer’s Dogs.David Berman - 1982 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 29:202-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Albert Camus.Ronald Aronson - 1962 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The 'Polis' as a society: Aristotle, John Rawls and the athenian social contract.J. Ober - 1993 - In Mogens Herman Hansen (ed.), The Ancient Greek city-state: symposium on the occasion of the 250th anniversary of the Royal Danish Academy of Sciences and Letters, July, 1-4 1992. Copenhagen: Commissioner, Munksgaard.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Schopenhauer and Spinoza.Henry Walter Brann - 1972 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 10 (2):181-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Schopenhauer's Critique of Spinoza's Pantheism, Optimism, and Egoism.Mor Segev - 2021 - In Yitzhak Y. Melamed (ed.), A Companion to Spinoza. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. pp. 557–567.
    Schopenhauer shares with Spinoza the basic idea that “the world exists by its own inner power and through itself”. Spinoza's system, Schopenhauer maintains, elaborately captures the observation, at the core of both pantheism and Schopenhauer's own theory, that all experienced phenomena share a single metaphysical substratum, and that in this sense everything is one. Any view or system of thought upholding optimism must confront the challenge of accounting for those features of the world that appear to be less than optimal. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Emendation to Fragment 13 of Aristotle's Protrepticus.A. H. Chroust - 1966 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 28:366-377.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Spinoza: lire la correspondance.P.-F. Moreau - 2004 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 1:3-8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle on Nature, Human Nature and Human Understanding.Mor Segev - 2017 - Rhizomata 5 (2):177-209.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Rhizomata Jahrgang: 5 Heft: 2 Seiten: 177-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Aristotle's Inclusivism.Roger Crisp - 1994 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12:111-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Megalopsychia: A Suggestion.Frederick A. Seddon - 1975 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 56 (1):31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Schopenhauer and Nietzsche: Honest Atheism, Dishonest Pessimism.David Berman - 1998 - In Christopher Janaway (ed.), Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche’s Educator. New York: Clarendon Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Anger as a Vice: A Maimonidean Critique of Aristotle's Ethics.Daniel H. Frank - 1990 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 7 (3):269 - 281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Nietzsche on Nihilism.João Constâncio - 2016 - In Andrea Bertino, Ekaterina Poljakova, Andreas Rupschus & Benjamin Alberts (eds.), Zur Philosophie der Orientierung. Boston: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 83-100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle on the Foundations of Sublunary Physics.M. F. Burnyeat - 2004 - In Frans A. J. de Haas & Jaap Mansfeld (eds.), Aristotle On generation and corruption, book 1: Symposium Aristotelicum. New York: Clarendon Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Self and Morality in Schopenhauer and Nietzsche.David Cooper - 1998 - In Christopher Janaway (ed.), Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche’s Educator. New York: Clarendon Press. pp. 214--215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Meaning of Aristotelian Magnanimity.Michael Pakaluk - 2004 - In David Sedley (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Xxvi: Summer 2004. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle "De Caelo" 279 a 18-35 , a "Fragment" of the Lost Aristotelian "On Philosophy".Anton-Hermann Chroust - 1975 - The Thomist 39 (2):332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Animal Ethics Based on Friendship.Barbro Frööding & Martin Peterson - 2011 - Journal of Animal Ethics 1 (1):58-69.
    This article discusses some aspects of animal ethics from an Aristotelian virtue ethics point of view. Because the notion of friendship (philia) is central to Aristotle’s ethical theory, the focus of the article is whether humans and animals can be friends. It is argued that new empirical findings in cognitive ethology indicate that animals actually do fulfill the Aristotelian condition for friendship based on mutual advantage. The practical ethical implications of these findings are discussed, and it is argued that eating (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Induction.T. Nagel - 1995 - In Ted Honderich (ed.), The Oxford companion to philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Searching for the Divine in Plato and Aristotle: Philosophical Theoria and Traditional Practice. By Julie K. Ward.Mor Segev - 2023 - Ancient Philosophy 43 (2):547-551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nietzsche's Use and Abuse of Schopenhauer's Moral Philosophy for Life.David E. Cartwright - 1998 - In Christopher Janaway (ed.), Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche’s Educator. New York: Clarendon Press. pp. 116--150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations