Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Individualism and the Mental.Tyler Burge - 2003 - In John Heil (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   706 citations  
  • Radical constructivism: Between realism and solipsism.Alberto Martínez‐Delgado - 2002 - Science Education 86 (6):840-855.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Individualism and the mental.Tyler Burge - 1979 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1):73-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1237 citations  
  • The meaning of 'meaning'.Hilary Putnam - 1975 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7:131-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1379 citations  
  • The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (2nd edition).David J. Chalmers - 1996 - Oxford University Press.
    The book is an extended study of the problem of consciousness. After setting up the problem, I argue that reductive explanation of consciousness is impossible , and that if one takes consciousness seriously, one has to go beyond a strict materialist framework. In the second half of the book, I move toward a positive theory of consciousness with fundamental laws linking the physical and the experiential in a systematic way. Finally, I use the ideas and arguments developed earlier to defend (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2046 citations  
  • The semantics of chemical education: constructivism, externalism and the language of chemistry. [REVIEW]Pedro J. Sánchez Gómez - 2011 - Foundations of Chemistry 15 (1):103-116.
    In this paper we present a semantic analysis of the application of didactic constructivism to chemical education. We show that the psychological basis of constructivism yield, when applied to chemistry, an internalist semantics for the chemical names. Since these names have been presented as typical examples of an externalism for kind terms, a fundamental incompatibility ensues. We study this situation, to conclude that it affects chemical education at every level. Finally, we present a preliminary analysis of this problem from the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Peirce's Index.Thomas A. Goudge - 1965 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 1 (2):52 - 70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Radical constructivism: a way of knowing and learning.Ernst von Glasersfeld - 1995 - Washington, D.C.: Falmer Press.
    Chapter Growing up Constructivist: Languages and Thoughtful People What is radical constructivism? It is an unconventional approach to the problems of ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind.Jerry A. Fodor - 1987 - MIT Press. Edited by Margaret A. Boden.
    Preface 1 Introduction: The Persistence of the Attitudes 2 Individualism and Supervenience 3 Meaning Holism 4 Meaning and the World Order Epilogue Creation Myth Appendix Why There Still Has to be a Language of Thought Notes References Author Index.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1512 citations  
  • Solipsistic semantics.Ernest Lepore & Barry Loewer - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):595-614.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Narrow content functionalism and the mind-body problem.Kenneth Taylor - 1989 - Noûs 23 (3):355-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The components of content.David J. Chalmers - 2002 - In David John Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. New York: Oxford University Press USA.
    [[This paper appears in my anthology _Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings_ (Oxford University Press, 2002), pp. 608-633. It is a heavily revised version of a paper first written in 1994 and revised in 1995. Sections 1, 7, 8, and 10 are similar to the old version, but the other sections are quite different. Because the old version has been widely cited, I have made it available (in its 1995 version) at http://consc.net/papers/content95.html.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • A modal argument for narrow content.Jerry A. Fodor - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (1):5-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Individualism and psychology.Tyler Burge - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (January):3-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   464 citations  
  • Phenomenal intentionality as the basis of mental content.Brian Loar - 2003 - In Martin Hahn & Björn T. Ramberg (eds.), Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge. MIT Press. pp. 229--258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  • Mental Causation.John Heil & Alfred R. Mele (eds.) - 1993 - Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    Common sense and philosophical tradition agree that mind makes a difference. What we do depends not only on how our bodies are put together, but also on what we think. Explaining how mind can make a difference has proved challenging, however. Some have urged that the project faces an insurmountable dilemma: either we concede that mentalistic explanations of behavior have only a pragmatic standing or we abandon our conception of the physical domain as causally autonomous. Although each option has its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind.Daniel C. Dennett - 1988 - Journal of Philosophy 85 (7):384-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   603 citations  
  • Narrow mental content.Curtis Brown - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Narrow mental content is a kind of mental content that does not depend on an individual's environment. Narrow content contrasts with “broad” or “wide” content, which depends on features of the individual's environment as well as on features of the individual. It is controversial whether there is any such thing as narrow content. Assuming that there is, it is also controversial what sort of content it is, what its relation to ordinary or “broad” content is, and how it is determined (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Individual and sociocultural views of learning in science education.John Leach & Phil Scott - 2003 - Science & Education 12 (1):91-113.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Social content and psychological content.Brian Loar - 1988 - In Robert H. Grimm & Daniel Davy Merrill (eds.), Contents of Thought. Tucson.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • Constructivist Model Building: Empirical Examples From Mathematics Education.C. Ulrich, E. S. Tillema, A. J. Hackenberg & A. Norton - 2014 - Constructivist Foundations 9 (3):328-339.
    Context: This paper outlines how radical constructivist theory has led to a particular methodological technique, developing second-order models of student thinking, that has helped mathematics educators to be more effective teachers of their students. Problem: The paper addresses the problem of how radical constructivist theory has been used to explain and engender more viable adaptations to the complexities of teaching and learning. Method: The paper presents empirical data from teaching experiments that illustrate the process of second-order model building. Results: The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Preservice Elementary Teachers’ Ideas About Scientific Practices.Amy Ricketts - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (10):2119-2135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mental Causation.John Heil & Alfred Mele - 1995 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 185 (1):105-106.
    Common sense and philosophical tradition agree that mind makes a difference. What we do depends not only on how our bodies are put together, but also on what we think. Explaining how mind can make a difference has proved challenging, however. Some have urged that the project faces an insurmountable dilemma: either we concede that mentalistic explanations of behavior have only a pragmatic standing or we abandon our conception of the physical domain as causally autonomous. Although each option has its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • The radical constructivist view of science.Ernst von Glasersfeld - 2001 - Foundations of Science 6 (1-3):31-43.
    From the constructivist perspective, science cannot transcend thedomain of experience. Scientific theories are seen as models that helpto order and manage that domain. As the experiential field expands,models are replaced by others based on novel conceptual constructs. Thepaper suggests the substitution of viability or functional fit forthe notions of Truth and objective representation of anexperiencer-independent reality. This by-passes the sceptics'incontrovertible arguments against certain real-world knowledge andproposes the Piagetian conception of cognition as the function thatgenerates ways and means for dealing with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Mediating mental models of metals: Acknowledging the priority of the learner's prior learning.Keith S. Taber - 2003 - Science Education 87 (5):732-758.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations