Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. An Unconnected Heap of Duties?David McNaughton - 2002 - In Philip Stratton-Lake (ed.), Ethical Intuitionism: Re-Evaluations. Oxford University Press UK.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Ulysses arrangements in psychiatry: a matter of good care?I. Gremmen, G. Widdershoven, A. Beekman, R. Zuijderhoudt & S. Sevenhuijsen - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (2):77-80.
    This article concerns the issue of how an ethic of care perspective may contribute to both normative theory and mental health care policy discussions on so called Ulysses arrangements, a special type of advance directives in psychiatry. The debate on Ulysses arrangements has predominantly been waged in terms of autonomy conceived of as the right to non-intervention. On the basis of our empirical investigations into the experiences of persons directly involved with Ulysses arrangements, we argue that a care ethics perspective (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Ethics without principles.Jonathan Dancy - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this much-anticipated book, Jonathan Dancy offers the only available full-scale treatment of particularism in ethics, a view with which he has been associated for twenty years. Dancy now presents particularism as the view that the possibility of moral thought and judgement does not in any way depend on an adequate supply of principles. He grounds this claim on a form of reasons-holism, holding that what is a reason in one case need not be any reason in another, and maintaining (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   673 citations  
  • On liberty: Examples of applications of the liberty principle.Richard Arneson - unknown
    Mill holds that in some of these cases the restriction of liberty that is proposed is permissible according to the liberty principle. In other cases, the proposed restriction violates the liberty principle as Mill understands it. (Mill first formulates the "liberty principle" on p. 9.).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How to justify enforcing a Ulysses contract when Ulysses is competent to refuse.John K. Davis - 2008 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 18 (1):pp. 87-106.
    Sometimes the mentally ill have sufficient mental capacity to refuse treatment competently, and others have a moral duty to respect their refusal. However, those with episodic mental disorders may wish to precommit themselves to treatment, using Ulysses contracts known as “mental health advance directives.” How can health care providers justify enforcing such contracts over an agent’s current, competent refusal? I argue that providers respect an agent’s autonomy not retrospectively—by reference to his or her past wishes—and not merely synchronically—so that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Advance directives in psychiatric care: a narrative approach.G. Widdershoven - 2001 - Journal of Medical Ethics 27 (2):92-97.
    Advance directives for psychiatric care are the subject of debate in a number of Western societies. By using psychiatric advance directives , it would be possible for mentally ill persons who are competent and with their disease in remission, and who want timely intervention in case of future mental crisis, to give prior authorisation to treatment at a later time when they are incompetent, have become non-compliant, and are refusing care. Thus the devastating consequences of recurrent psychosis could be minimised.Ulysses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Ethics and Intuitions: A Reply to Singer.Joakim Sandberg & Niklas Juth - 2011 - The Journal of Ethics 15 (3):209-226.
    In a recent paper, Peter Singer suggests that some interesting new findings in experimental moral psychology support what he has contended all along—namely that intuitions should play little or no role in adequate justifications of normative ethical positions. Not only this but, according to Singer, these findings point to a central flaw in the method (or epistemological theory) of reflective equilibrium used by many contemporary moral philosophers. In this paper, we try to defend reflective equilibrium from Singer’s attack and, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Cake or death? Ending confusions about asymmetries between consent and refusal.Rob Lawlor - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (11):748-754.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Many Faces of Competency.James F. Drane - 2012 - Hastings Center Report 15 (2):17-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • The Debate over Risk‐related Standards of Competence.Ian Wilks - 1997 - Bioethics 11 (5):413-426.
    This discussion paper continues the debate over risk‐related standards of mental competence which appears in Bioethics 5. Dan Brock there defends an approach to mental competence in patients which defines it as being relative to differing standards, more or less rigorous depending on the degree of risk involved in proposed treatments. But Mark Wicclair raises a problem for this approach: if significantly different levels of risk attach, respectively, to accepting and refusing the same treatment, then it is possible, on this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Protecting autonomy as authenticity using Ulysses contracts.Theo Van Willigenburg & Patrick Delaere - 2005 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 30 (4):395 – 409.
    Pre-commitment directives or Ulysses contracts are often defended as instruments that may strengthen the autonomous self-control of episodically disordered psychiatric patients. Autonomy is understood in this context in terms of sovereignty ("governing" or "managing" oneself). After critically analyzing this idea of autonomy in the context of various forms of self-commitment and pre-commitment, we argue that what is at stake in using Ulysses contracts in psychiatry is not autonomy as sovereignty, but autonomy as authenticity. Pre-commitment directives do not function to protect (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Ulysses Contracts in Medicine.Tom Walker - 2012 - Law and Philosophy 31 (1):77-98.
    Ulysses contracts are a method by which one person binds himself by agreeing to be bound by others. In medicine such contracts have primarily been discussed as ways of treating people with episodic mental illnesses, where the features of the illness are such that they now judge that they will refuse treatment at the time it is needed. Enforcing Ulysses contracts in these circumstances would require medical professionals to override the express refusal of the patient at the time treatment is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Intricate Ethics: Rights, Responsibilities, and Permissible Harm.F. M. Kamm - 2006 - New York, US: Oxford University Press USA.
    In Intricate Ethics, Kamm questions the moral importance of some non-consequentialist distinctions and then introduces and argues for the moral importance of other distinctions. The first section discusses nonconsequentialist ethical theory and the trolley problem; the second deals with the notions of moral status and rights; the third takes up the issues of responsibility and complicity and the possible moral significance of distance; and the fourth section analyzes the views of others in the non-consequentialist and consequentialist camps.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Asymmetrical competence.Ian Wilks - 1999 - Bioethics 13 (2):154–159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Intricate Ethics: Rights, Responsibilities, and Permissible Harm, by F. M. Kamm.R. Lawlor - 2009 - Mind 118 (472):1149-1152.
    (No abstract is available for this citation).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Freedom not to be free.David Archard - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161):453.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Reviving Ulysses contracts.Ryan Spellecy - 2003 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 13 (4):373-392.
    : Ulysses contracts have faced paternalism objections since they first were proposed. Since the contracts are designed to override a present request from a legally competent patient in favor of a past request made by that patient, enforcement of these contracts was argued to be unjustifiable strong paternalism. Recent legal developments and new theories of practical reasoning suggest that the discussion of Ulysses contracts should be revived. This paper argues that with a proper understanding of the future-directed planning embodied in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Intuitions and moral theorizing.Brad Hooker - 2002 - In Philip Stratton-Lake (ed.), Ethical Intuitionism: Re-Evaluations. Oxford University Press UK. pp. 76--161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Freedom not to be free: The case of the slavery contract in J. S. mill's on liberty.David Archard - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161):453-465.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations