Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Kantian Lessons about Mind, Meaning, and Rationality.Robert Brandom - 2006 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 44 (S1):49-71.
    Kant's innovative normative characterization of what one is doing in judging is appealed to as the basis of a story about how he moves from an inferential to a representational characterization of the contents of judgment. His normative notion of freedom and his demarcation of the normative in terms of autonomy are connected to his account of the status of modal concepts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Metaphysical Disputes and Metalinguistic Negotiation.Amie L. Thomasson - 2016 - Analytic Philosophy 57 (4):1-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Characterizing generics are material inference tickets: a proof-theoretic analysis.Preston Stovall - 2019 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy (5):668-704.
    An adequate semantics for generic sentences must stake out positions across a range of contested territory in philosophy and linguistics. For this reason the study of generic sentences is a venue for investigating different frameworks for understanding human rationality as manifested in linguistic phenomena such as quantification, classification of individuals under kinds, defeasible reasoning, and intensionality. Despite the wide variety of semantic theories developed for generic sentences, to date these theories have been almost universally model-theoretic and representational. This essay outlines (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes.Leslie Stevenson - 1970 - Philosophical Quarterly 20 (78):86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1: The Dawn of Analysis.Scott Soames - 2003 - Princeton University Press.
    Introduction to the Two Volumes xi PART ONE: G. E. MOORE ON ETHICS, EPISTEMOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS 1 CHAPTER 1 Common Sense and Philosophical Analysis 3 CHAPTER 2 Moore on Skepticism, Perception, and Knowledge 12 CHAPTER 3 Moore on Goodness and the Foundations of Ethics 34 CHAPTER 4 The Legacies and Lost Opportunities of Moore’s Ethics 71 Suggested Further Reading 89 PART TWO: BERTRAND RUSSELL ON LOGICAL AND LINGUISTIC ANALYSIS 91 CHAPTER 5 Logical Form, Grammatical Form, and the Theory of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Naming and saying.Wilfrid Sellars - 1962 - Philosophy of Science 29 (1):7-26.
    The essay adopts the Tractarian view that configurations of objects are expressed by configurations of names. Two alternatives are considered: The objects in atomic facts are (1) without exception particulars; (2) one or more particulars plus a universal (Gustav Bergmann). On (1) a mode of configuration is always an empirical relation: on (2) it is the logical nexus of 'exemplification.' It is argued that (1) is both Wittgenstein's view in the Tractatus and correct. It is also argued that exemplification is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Meaning as functional classification.Wilfrid Sellars - 1974 - Synthese 27 (3-4):417 - 437.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Grammar and existence: A preface to ontology.Wilfrid Sellars - 1960 - Mind 69 (276):499-533.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Evolutionary Naturalism. [REVIEW]Maurice Picard - 1922 - Journal of Philosophy 19 (21):582-587.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Concepts as involving laws and inconceivable without them.Wilfrid Sellars - 1948 - Philosophy of Science 15 (October):287-313.
    Formal implication is usually represented by symbolization such as ‘ φx ⊃ Ψx,’ which may be read, “for all values of ‘x’, φx implies Ψx.” If the values of the variable ‘x’, in ‘φx’ and ‘Ψx’ be ‘x1’ ‘x2’ ‘x3’, etc., then … ‘φx’ formally implies ‘Ψx’ if and only if, whatever values of ‘x’, ‘xn’, be chosen, ‘φxn’ materially implies ‘Ψxn’ …However, this still leaves it doubtful which of two possible interpretations of expressions having the form ‘ φx ⊃ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • A History of American Philosophy. [REVIEW]Harold A. Larrabee - 1947 - Journal of Philosophy 44 (10):272-277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mind and World.Hilary Putnam - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (2):267.
    Quine has spoken of bringing our beliefs about the world before “the tribunal of experience.” In Mind and World, McDowell agrees that this is what we must do, but he argues forcefully that Quine’s conception of experience as nothing more than a neuronal cause of verbal responses loses the whole idea that experiences can justify beliefs. McDowell’s overarching aim is to determine conditions that experience must satisfy if it is to be genuinely a tribunal.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • James, Dewey, and the Reflex Arc.D. C. Phillips - 1971 - Journal of the History of Ideas 32 (4):555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Issues of Pragmaticism.Charles S. Peirce - 1905 - The Monist 15 (4):481-499.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • What Pragmatism Is.Charles S. Peirce - 1905 - The Monist 15 (2):161-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Neo-positivist metaphysics.Alyssa Ney - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 160 (1):53-78.
    Some philosophers argue that many contemporary debates in metaphysics are “illegitimate,” “shallow,” or “trivial,” and that “contemporary analytic metaphysics, a professional activity engaged in by some extremely intelligent and morally serious people, fails to qualify as part of the enlightened pursuit of objective truth, and should be discontinued” (Ladyman and Ross, Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized , 2007 ). Many of these critics are explicit about their sympathies with Rudolf Carnap and his circle, calling themselves ‘neo-positivists’ or ‘neo-Carnapians.’ Yet (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Does American Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?Bruce Kuklick - 1985 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 19:177-189.
    When I write about ‘American philosophy’ in this paper, I refer not to the practice of philosophizing in a certain geographic area during a certain time. Rather I mean a scholarly field defined by certain conventions, standard arguments, and major works. I hope primarily to show that that area of inquiry is befuddled. I also want to suggest, however, that it may be unhelpful to try to write about the practice of philosophizing in a certain geographic area—the continental United States—in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Will to Believe, and other Essays in Popular Philosophy.William James - 1897 - Philosophical Review 6 (3):331.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • Carnap's Metaontology.Matti Eklund - 2011 - Noûs 47 (2):229-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The Influence of Darwinism on Philosophy.John Dewey - 2018 - Nóema 9.
    That the publication of the Origin of Species marked an epoch in the development of the natural sciences is well known to the layman. That the combination of the very words origin and species embodied an intellectual revolt and introduced a new intellectual temper is easily overlooked by the expert. The conceptions that had reigned in the philosophy of nature and knowledge for two thousand years, the conceptions that had become the familiar furniture of the mind, rested on the assumption (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • A Linguistic Turn in the Philosophy of Normativity?John Broome - 2015 - Analytic Philosophy 57 (1):1-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The pragmatist enlightenment (and its problematic semantics).Robert B. Brandom - 2004 - European Journal of Philosophy 12 (1):1–16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Some Pragmatist Themes in Hegel's Idealism: Negotiation and Administration in Hegel's Account of the Structure and Content of Conceptual Norms.Robert B. Brandom - 1999 - European Journal of Philosophy 7 (2):164-189.
    Some Pragmatist Themes in Hegel’s Idealism:Negotiation and Administration in Hegel’sAccount of the Structure and Content ofConceptual NormsRobert B. BrandomThis paper could equally well have been titled ‘Some Idealist Themes in Hegel’sPragmatism’. Both idealism and pragmatism are capacious concepts, encompassingmany distinguishable theses. I will focus on one pragmatist thesis and one ideal-ist thesis (though we will come within sight of some others). The pragmatistthesis (what I will call ‘the semantic pragmatist thesis’) is that the use of conceptsdetermines their content, that is, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Reason in philosophy: animating ideas.Robert Brandom - 2009 - Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    This is a paradigmatic work of contemporary philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • Kantian Lessons about Mind, Meaning, and Rationality.Robert Brandom - 2006 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 44 (S1):49-71.
    Kant's innovative normative characterization of what one is doing in judging is appealed to as the basis of a story about how he moves from an inferential to a representational characterization of the contents of judgment. His normative notion of freedom and his demarcation of the normative in terms of autonomy are connected to his account of the status of modal concepts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ontology after Carnap.Stephan Blatti & Sandra Lapointe - 2016 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 71 (1):166-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Normativity in Neo‐Kantianism: Its Rise and Fall.Frederick C. Beiser - 2009 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 17 (1):9 – 27.
    This article discusses the historical background to the concept of normativity which has a wide use in contemporary philosophy. It locates the origin of that concept in the Southwestern Neo-Kantian school, the writings of Windelband, Rickert and Lask. The Southwestern school made the concept of normativity central to epistemology, ethics and the interpretation of German idealism. It was their solution to the threats of psycologism and historicism. However, Windelband, Rickert and Lask found difficulties with the concept which eventually forced them (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Mind and World.John McDowell - 1996 - Philosophical Quarterly 46 (182):99-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   992 citations  
  • Wilfrid Sellars. [REVIEW]Willem DeVries - 2005 - Review of Metaphysics 61 (4):854-855.
    A brief "book note" on James O'Shea's "Wilfrid Sellars".
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Ontological anti-realism.David J. Chalmers - 2009 - In David Chalmers, David Manley & Ryan Wasserman (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford University Press.
    The basic question of ontology is “What exists?”. The basic question of metaontology is: are there objective answers to the basic question of ontology? Here ontological realists say yes, and ontological anti-realists say no. (Compare: The basic question of ethics is “What is right?”. The basic question of metaethics is: are there objective answers to the basic question of ethics? Here moral realists say yes, and moral anti-realists say no.) For example, the ontologist may ask: Do numbers exist? The Platonist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • Was pragmatism the successor to idealism?Terry Pinkard - 2007 - In Cheryl Misak (ed.), New pragmatists. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals.Immanuel Kant - 1785/2002 - In Practical Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 37-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   811 citations  
  • Ambitious, yet modest, metaphysics.Thomas Hofweber - 2009 - In David Chalmers, David Manley & Ryan Wasserman (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford University Press. pp. 260--289.
    There is a long history of worrying about whether or not metaphysics is a legitimate philosophical discipline. Traditionally such worries center around issues of meaning and epistemological concerns. Do the metaphysical questions have any meaning? Can metaphysical methodology lead to knowledge? But these questions are, in my opinion, not as serious as they have sometimes (historically) been taken to be. What is much more concerning is another set of worries about metaphysics, which I take to the greatest threat to metaphysics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  • James's Will-to-Believe Doctrine: A Heretical View.James C. S. Wernham - 1988 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 24 (3):423-427.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Abstract Entities.Wilfrid Sellars - 1963 - Review of Metaphysics 16 (4):627 - 671.
    Now the thesis that the universal redness is the linguistic type ⋅red⋅ has the ring of absurdity. There are several ways in which this discomfort can be expressed I shall open my argument by formulating an objection which, by cutting deeper than most, leads to a firm foundation for a restatement and defense of the thesis.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • The identity approach to the mind-body problem.Wilfrid Sellars - 1965 - Review of Metaphysics 18 (3):430-51.
    1. My primary aim in this paper is to set the stage for a discussion of some of the central themes in the so-called "identity" approach to the mind-body problem. I have particularly in mind Herbert Feigl's elaborate statement and defense of this approach in Volume II of the Minnesota Studies. A secondary, but more constructive, purpose is to bring out some of the reasons which incline me to think that the theory is either very exciting but false, or true (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • C. I. Lewis and the Given.Eric Dayton - 1995 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 31 (2):254 - 284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Rise of American Philosophy: Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1860-1930.Bruce Kuklick - 1979 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10 (3):204-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • William James: In the Maelstrom of American Modernism.Robert D. Richardson - 2008 - The Pluralist 3 (1):128-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • William James at the Boundaries: Philosophy, Science, and the Geography of Knowledge.Francesca Bordogna - 2009 - Journal of the History of Biology 42 (4):833-836.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • A History of Philosophy in America 1720-2000.Bruce Kuklick - 2004 - Philosophy 79 (308):348-350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century.Scott Soames - 2005 - Filosoficky Casopis 53:794-798.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Sellars the Post-Kantian?Terry Pinkard - 2007 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 92 (1):21-52.
    In Kant's "fact of reason," there is an apparent paradox of our being subject to laws of which we must regard ourselves as the author, while at the same time being normatively bound by the same laws that we cannot see ourselves as authoring. Working out the implications of this apparent paradox generated much of the response to Kant in post-Kantian idealism. Wilfrid Sellars notes the same paradox when he speaks of the "paradox of man's encounter with himself" in "Philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations