Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Translator's Introduction.[author unknown] - 1974 - Politics and Society 4 (2):192-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • (1 other version)Reference and Consciousness.John Campbell - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (2):490-494.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   286 citations  
  • Kant's Theory of Mental Activity.William H. Baumer - 1964 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 25 (1):133-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Kantian Intuitions.Jaakko Hintikka - 1972 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 15:341.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (1 other version)What are these Familiar Words Doing Here?A. W. Moore - 2002 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 51:147-171.
    This essay is concerned with six linguistic moves that we commonly make, each of which is considered in turn. These are: stating rules of representation; representing things categorically; mentioning expressions; saying truly or falsely how things are; saying vaguely how things are; and stating rules of rules of representation. A common-sense view is defended of what is involved in our doing each of these six things against a much more sceptical view emanating from the idea that linguistic behavior is fundamentally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Philosophical Foundations of Physics. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science.Rudolf Carnap & Martin Gardner - 1966 - Synthese 17 (1):366-367.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • (1 other version)Truth by Convention.W. V. Quine - 1976 - In Willard Van Orman Quine (ed.), The ways of paradox, and other essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. pp. 90–124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   190 citations  
  • (1 other version)Steps Toward a Constructive Nominalism.Nelson Goodman & W. V. Quine - 1947 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 13 (1):49-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • (1 other version)Reason, Truth and History.Kathleen Okruhlik - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (4):692-694.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   498 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Naming and Necessity.Saul Kripke - 1980 - Critica 17 (49):69-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1926 citations  
  • Reflections On Kant’s Concept Of Space.Lisa Shabel - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (1):45-57.
    In this paper, I investigate an important aspect of Kant’s theory of pure sensible intuition. I argue that, according to Kant, a pure concept of space warrants and constrains intuitions of finite regions of space. That is, an a priori conceptual representation of space provides a governing principle for all spatial construction, which is necessary for mathematical demonstration as Kant understood it.Author Keywords: Kant; Space; Pure sensible intuition; Philosophy of mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Exorcising the Philosophical Tradition.Michael Friedman - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):427-467.
    One of the most interesting aspects of McDowell’s very interesting book is the way in which it locates the problems of late-twentieth-century Anglo-American philosophy within the historical development of the Western philosophical tradition. Beginning with an opposition between Coherentism and the Myth of the Given exemplified in recent work of Donald Davidson’s, McDowell proceeds to frame his discussion in terms of the Kantian distinction between concepts and intuitions, understanding and sensibility, spontaneity and receptivity. McDowell’s basic idea is that we can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Lawfulness without a Law.Hannah Ginsborg - 1997 - Philosophical Topics 25 (1):37-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Two Dogmas about Logical Empiricism.Alan Richardson - 1997 - Philosophical Topics 25 (2):145-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Heidegger's Crisis: Philosophy and Politics in Nazi Germany.Charles Guignon & Hans Sluga - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (2):293.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Kant and the Capacity to Judge.Kenneth R. Westphal & Beatrice Longuenesse - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (4):645.
    Kant famously declares that “although all our cognition commences with experience, … it does not on that account all arise from experience”. This marks Kant’s disagreement with empiricism, and his contention that human knowledge and experience require both sensation and the use of certain a priori concepts, the Categories. However, this is only the surface of Kant’s much deeper, though neglected view about the nature of reason and judgment. Kant holds that even our a priori concepts are acquired, not from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   230 citations  
  • (1 other version)Historical Dictionary of Wittgenstein's Philosophy.Duncan Richter - 2004 - Lanham, MD, USA: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    This second edition of Historical Dictionary of Wittgenstein's Philosophy covers the history of this philosophy through a chronology, an introductory essay, and an extensive bibliography. The dictionary section has over 300 cross-referenced entries on every aspect of his work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Saying What You Really Want to Say: Wittgenstein, Gödel and the Trisection of the Angle.Juliet Floyd - 1995 - In Jaakko Hintikka (ed.), From Dedekind to Gödel: The Foundations of Mathematics in the Early Twentieth Century, Synthese Library Vol. 251 (Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 373-426.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (trans. Pears and McGuinness).Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1921 - New York,: Routledge. Edited by Luciano Bazzocchi & P. M. S. Hacker.
    Perhaps the most important work of philosophy written in the twentieth century, the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus first appeared in 1921 and was the only philosophical work that Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) published during his lifetime. Written in short, carefully numbered paragraphs of extreme compression and brilliance, it immediately convinced many of its readers and captivated the imagination of all. Its chief influence, at first, was on the Logical Positivists of the 1920s and 30s, but many other philosophers were stimulated by its philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • Geometry, construction, and intuition in Kant and his successors.Michael Friedman - 2000 - In Gila Sher & Richard Tieszen (eds.), Between logic and intuition: essays in honor of Charles Parsons. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 186--218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Singular Terms and Intuitions In Kant’s Epistemology.Manley Thompson - 1972 - Review of Metaphysics 26 (2):314 - 343.
    Kant's distinction between intuitive and discursive knowledge precludes his giving intuitions linguistic representation. Singular terms represent concepts given what kant calls a 'singular use' and are analyzable as definite descriptions. That the object described exists and that there is only one such object can be given linguistic representation only through an explicit assertion of existence and uniqueness. As an intuitionist in mathematics kant holds that mathematics proclaims the constructibility and not the existence of its objects.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Kant on Intuition in Geometry.Emily Carson - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (4):489 - 512.
    It's well-known that Kant believed that intuition was central to an account of mathematical knowledge. What that role is and how Kant argues for it are, however, still open to debate. There are, broadly speaking, two tendencies in interpreting Kant's account of intuition in mathematics, each emphasizing different aspects of Kant's general doctrine of intuition. On one view, most recently put forward by Michael Friedman, this central role for intuition is a direct result of the limitations of the syllogistic logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Must we show what we cannot say?James Conant - 1989 - In R. Fleming & M. Payne (eds.), The Senses of Stanley Cavell. Bucknell. pp. 242--83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Replies and Systematic Expositions.Rudolf Carnap - 1963 - In ¸ Iteschilpp:Prc. pp. 859--1013.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Epistemology Naturalized.W. V. Quine - 1969 - In Willard van Orman Quine (ed.), Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. Columbia University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   519 citations  
  • (5 other versions)Two Dogmas of Empiricism.Willard V. O. Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):20–43.
    Modern empiricism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact, and truth which are synthetic, or grounded in fact. The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience. Both dogmas, I shall argue, are ill founded. One effect of abandoning them is, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1358 citations  
  • On the Textual Authenticity of Kant's Logic.Terry Boswell - 1988 - History and Philosophy of Logic 9 (2):193-203.
    Philological background information is presented on the origin and composition of the text generally known as Kant's Logic. The text, which was not in the strict sense of the word written by Kant himself, but rather assembled by another writer whom Kant had authorized to do so on his behalf, is a mixture of materials, not all of which originate directly from Kant, and cannot claim full authenticity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Mind and World.Huw Price & John McDowell - 1994 - Philosophical Books 38 (3):169-181.
    How do rational minds make contact with the world? The empiricist tradition sees a gap between mind and world, and takes sensory experience, fallible as it is, to provide our only bridge across that gap. In its crudest form, for example, the traditional idea is that our minds consult an inner realm of sensory experience, which provides us with evidence about the nature of external reality. Notoriously, however, it turns out to be far from clear that there is any viable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1032 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Natural kinds.Willard V. Quine - 1969 - In Willard van Orman Quine (ed.), Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. Columbia University Press. pp. 114-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   169 citations  
  • (2 other versions)A coherence theory of truth and knowledge.Donald Davidson - 1986 - In Ernest LePore (ed.), Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Cambridge: Blackwell. pp. 307-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   492 citations  
  • (1 other version)Philosophical grammar.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1974 - Oxford [Eng.]: Blackwell. Edited by Rush Rhees.
    pt. 1. The proposition and its sense.--pt. 2. On logic and mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   221 citations  
  • Russell, idealism, and the emergence of analytic philosophy.Peter Hylton - 1990 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Analytic philosophy has become the dominant philosophical tradition in the English-speaking world. This book illuminates that tradition through a historical examination of a crucial period in its formation: the rejection of Idealism by Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore at the beginning of the twentieth century, and the subsequent development of Russell's thought in the period before the First World War.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  • (1 other version)Selected logic papers.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1995 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Selected Logic Papers, long out of print and now reissued with eight additional essays, includes much of the author's important work on mathematical logic and ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Kant's philosophy of arithmetic.Charles Parsons - 1982 - In Ralph Charles Sutherland Walker (ed.), Kant on Pure Reason. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • McDowell’s Kantianism.John Macfarlane - 2004 - Theoria 70 (2-3):250-265.
    In recent work, John McDowell has urged that we resurrect the Kantian thesis that concepts without intuitions are empty. I distinguish two forms of the thesis: a strong form that applies to all concepts and a weak form that is limited to empirical concepts. Because McDowell rejects Kant’s philosophy of mathematics, he can accept only the weaker form of the thesis. But this position is unstable. The reasoning behind McDowell’s insistence that empirical concepts can have content only if they are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Foundations of Logic and Mathematics.M. Kokoszyńska - 1939 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):117-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Was Carnap entirely wrong, after all?Howard Stein - 1992 - Synthese 93 (1-2):275-295.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Carnap and logical truth.Willard van Orman Quine - 1954 - Synthese 12 (4):350--74.
    Kant's question 'How are synthetic judgments a priori possible?' pre- cipitated the Critique of Pure Reason. Question and answer notwith- standing, Mill and others persisted in doubting that such judgments were possible at all. At length some of Kant's own clearest purported.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   211 citations  
  • Epistemology in the Aufbau.Michael Friedman - 1992 - Synthese 93 (1-2):15 - 57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Russell and Kant.J. Alberto Coffa - 1981 - Synthese 46 (2):247 - 263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Knowing and asserting.Timothy Williamson - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):489-523.
    This paper aims to identify the constitutive rule of assertion, conceived by analogy with the rules of a game. That assertion has such rules is by no means obvious; perhaps it is more like a natural phenomenon than it seems. One way to find out is by supposing that it has such rules, in order to see where the hypothesis leads and what it explains. That will be done here. The hypothesis is not perfectly clear, of course, but we have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   331 citations  
  • Extending knowledge and `fruitful concepts': Fregean themes in the foundations of mathematics.Jamie Tappenden - 1995 - Noûs 29 (4):427-467.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Points of view.Adrian William Moore - 1987 - Philosophical Quarterly 37 (146):1-20.
    A. W. Moore argues in this bold, unusual, and ambitious book that it is possible to think about the world from no point of view. His argument involves discussion of a very wide range of fundamental philosophical issues, including the nature of persons, the subject-matter of mathematics, realism and anti-realism, value, the inexpressible, and God. The result is a powerful critique of our own finitude.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Between metaphysics and nonsense: Elucidation in Wittgenstein's tractatus.Marie McGinn - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (197):491-513.
    There are currently two readings of Tractatus, the metaphysical and the therapeutic. I argue that neither of these is satisfactory. I develop a third reading, the elucidatory reading. This shares the therapeutic interpretation’s emphasis on the idea that Wittgenstein’s remarks are intended to work on the reader, but instead of seeing these remarks as directed (problematically) at revealing their own nonsensical status, I take the remarks to be aimed at bringing a certain order to the reader’s perception of language. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Frege, Kant, and the logic in logicism.John MacFarlane - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (1):25-65.
    Let me start with a well-known story. Kant held that logic and conceptual analysis alone cannot account for our knowledge of arithmetic: “however we might turn and twist our concepts, we could never, by the mere analysis of them, and without the aid of intuition, discover what is the sum [7+5]” (KrV, B16). Frege took himself to have shown that Kant was wrong about this. According to Frege’s logicist thesis, every arithmetical concept can be defined in purely logical terms, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • Logic in the twenties: The nature of the quantifier.Warren D. Goldfarb - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (3):351-368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • Kant's "argument from geometry".Lisa Shabel - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (2):195-215.
    : Kant's 'argument from geometry' is usually interpreted to be a regressive transcendental argument in support of the claim that we have a pure intuition of space. In this paper I defend an alternative interpretation of this argument according to which it is rather a progressive synthetic argument meant to identify and establish the essential role of pure spatial intuition in geometric cognition. In the course of reinterpreting the 'argument from geometry' I reassess the arguments of the Aesthetic and illustrate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Empiricism and the philosophy of mind.Wilfrid Sellars - 1956 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1:253-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1234 citations  
  • Having the world in view: Sellars, Kant, and intentionality.John Mcdowell - 1998 - Journal of Philosophy 95 (9):431-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   194 citations  
  • The intentionality all-stars.John Haugeland - 1990 - Philosophical Perspectives 4:383-427.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations