Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Foundations of Logic and Mathematics.M. Kokoszyńska - 1939 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):117-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Translator's Introduction.[author unknown] - 1974 - Politics and Society 4 (2):192-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Michael Friedman, A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger. [REVIEW]Gottfried Gabriel - 2003 - Erkenntnis 59 (1):125-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (trans. Pears and McGuinness).Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1961 - Routledge.
    Perhaps the most important work of philosophy written in the twentieth century, the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus first appeared in 1921 and was the only philosophical work that Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) published during his lifetime. Written in short, carefully numbered paragraphs of extreme compression and brilliance, it immediately convinced many of its readers and captivated the imagination of all. Its chief influence, at first, was on the Logical Positivists of the 1920s and 30s, but many other philosophers were stimulated by its philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • Geometry, construction, and intuition in Kant and his successors.Michael Friedman - 2000 - In Gila Sher & Richard Tieszen (eds.), Between logic and intuition: essays in honor of Charles Parsons. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 186--218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Sellars on Kantian intuitions.Mihael Woods - 1984 - Philosophia 14 (1-2):137-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kant's Theory of Mental Activity.William H. Baumer - 1964 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 25 (1):133-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Logic.Kirk D. Wilson, Immanuel Kant, Robert S. Hartman & Wolfgang Schwarz - 1976 - Philosophical Review 85 (1):97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Knowing and asserting.Timothy Williamson - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):489-523.
    This paper aims to identify the constitutive rule of assertion, conceived by analogy with the rules of a game. That assertion has such rules is by no means obvious; perhaps it is more like a natural phenomenon than it seems. One way to find out is by supposing that it has such rules, in order to see where the hypothesis leads and what it explains. That will be done here. The hypothesis is not perfectly clear, of course, but we have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   329 citations  
  • Introduction to the Foundations of Mathematics. [REVIEW]Ernest Nagel - 1953 - Journal of Philosophy 50 (19):591-593.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kant and the Capacity to Judge.Kenneth R. Westphal & Beatrice Longuenesse - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (4):645.
    Kant famously declares that “although all our cognition commences with experience, … it does not on that account all arise from experience”. This marks Kant’s disagreement with empiricism, and his contention that human knowledge and experience require both sensation and the use of certain a priori concepts, the Categories. However, this is only the surface of Kant’s much deeper, though neglected view about the nature of reason and judgment. Kant holds that even our a priori concepts are acquired, not from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   230 citations  
  • Synthesis and Transcendental Idealism.Ralph C. S. Walker - 1985 - Kant Studien 76 (1-4):14-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On a priori truth.Manley Thompson - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (8):458-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On the Textual Authenticity of Kant's Logic.Terry Boswell - 1988 - History and Philosophy of Logic 9 (2):193-203.
    Philological background information is presented on the origin and composition of the text generally known as Kant's Logic. The text, which was not in the strict sense of the word written by Kant himself, but rather assembled by another writer whom Kant had authorized to do so on his behalf, is a mixture of materials, not all of which originate directly from Kant, and cannot claim full authenticity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Extending knowledge and `fruitful concepts': Fregean themes in the foundations of mathematics.Jamie Tappenden - 1995 - Noûs 29 (4):427-467.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism.John Heil - 1986 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (2):331-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • The Bounds of sense. An essay on Kant's critique of pure reason.Walter H. Capps - 1969 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 29 (3):470-471.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Was Carnap entirely wrong, after all?Howard Stein - 1992 - Synthese 93 (1-2):275-295.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Kant on Marks and the Immediacy of Intuition.Houston Smit - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (2):235-266.
    The distinction between concept and intuition is of the utmost importance for understanding Kant’s critical philosophy. For, as Kant himself claimed, all the distinctive claims of this philosophy rest on, and develop out of, a detailed account of the way all our cognition of things requires both intuitions and concepts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Reflections On Kant’s Concept Of Space.Lisa Shabel - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (1):45-57.
    In this paper, I investigate an important aspect of Kant’s theory of pure sensible intuition. I argue that, according to Kant, a pure concept of space warrants and constrains intuitions of finite regions of space. That is, an a priori conceptual representation of space provides a governing principle for all spatial construction, which is necessary for mathematical demonstration as Kant understood it.Author Keywords: Kant; Space; Pure sensible intuition; Philosophy of mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kant's "argument from geometry".Lisa Shabel - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (2):195-215.
    : Kant's 'argument from geometry' is usually interpreted to be a regressive transcendental argument in support of the claim that we have a pure intuition of space. In this paper I defend an alternative interpretation of this argument according to which it is rather a progressive synthetic argument meant to identify and establish the essential role of pure spatial intuition in geometric cognition. In the course of reinterpreting the 'argument from geometry' I reassess the arguments of the Aesthetic and illustrate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Objectivity in aesthetic judgement: Eva Schaper on Kant.Anthony Savile - 1981 - British Journal of Aesthetics 21 (4):363-369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Carnaps 'Aufbau' in kantianischer Sicht.Werner Sauer - 1985 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 23 (1):19-35.
    Es wird versucht, einige Aspekte von Carnaps Werk Der logische Auflyau der Welt vor dem Hintergrund des Kantianismus zu betrachten, insbesondere die Strukturalismusthese, das Verhältnis von Gegebenem und Konstruiertem und den Wirklichkeitsbegriff; das Ergebnis geht dahin, daß sich mehr Gemeinsamkeiten mit der kantianischen Tradition zeigen als es von einem klassischen Werk des Neopositivismus zu erwarten wäre.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Two Dogmas about Logical Empiricism.Alan Richardson - 1997 - Philosophical Topics 25 (2):145-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays.Yehoshua Bar-Hillel - 1967 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 28 (4):596-600.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   158 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.Willard V. O. Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):20–43.
    Modern empiricism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact, and truth which are synthetic, or grounded in fact. The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience. Both dogmas, I shall argue, are ill founded. One effect of abandoning them is, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1341 citations  
  • Truth by Convention.W. V. Quine - 1976 - In Willard Van Orman Quine (ed.), The ways of paradox, and other essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. pp. 90–124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   190 citations  
  • From a Logical Point of View.Richard M. Martin - 1955 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 15 (4):574-575.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   566 citations  
  • Carnap and logical truth.Willard van Orman Quine - 1954 - Synthese 12 (4):350--74.
    Kant's question 'How are synthetic judgments a priori possible?' pre- cipitated the Critique of Pure Reason. Question and answer notwith- standing, Mill and others persisted in doubting that such judgments were possible at all. At length some of Kant's own clearest purported.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   213 citations  
  • Reason, Truth and History.Kathleen Okruhlik - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (4):692-694.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   498 citations  
  • Erscheinung bei Kant: Ein Problem der Kritik der Reinen Vernunft.Gerold Prauss - 1971 - Berlin,: de Gruyter.
    The series, founded in 1970, publishes works which either combine studies in the history of philosophy with a systematic approach or bring together systematic studies with reconstructions from the history of philosophy. Monographs are published in English as well as in German. The founding editors are Erhard Scheibe (editor until 1991), Günther Patzig (until 1999) and Wolfgang Wieland (until 2003). From 1990 to 2007, the series had been co-edited by Jürgen Mittelstraß.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Kant’s Theory of Form: An Essay on the Critique of Pure Reason.T. K. Seung - 1984 - Noûs 18 (2):382-385.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Arithmetic and the categories.Charles Parsons - 1984 - Topoi 3 (2):109-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • What are these Familiar Words Doing Here?A. W. Moore - 2002 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 51:147-171.
    This essay is concerned with six linguistic moves that we commonly make, each of which is considered in turn. These are: stating rules of representation; representing things categorically; mentioning expressions; saying truly or falsely how things are; saying vaguely how things are; and stating rules of rules of representation. A common-sense view is defended of what is involved in our doing each of these six things against a much more sceptical view emanating from the idea that linguistic behavior is fundamentally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Points of view.Adrian William Moore - 1987 - Philosophical Quarterly 37 (146):1-20.
    A. W. Moore argues in this bold, unusual, and ambitious book that it is possible to think about the world from no point of view. His argument involves discussion of a very wide range of fundamental philosophical issues, including the nature of persons, the subject-matter of mathematics, realism and anti-realism, value, the inexpressible, and God. The result is a powerful critique of our own finitude.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Kant's Transcendental Psychology.Ralf Meerbote & Patricia Kitcher - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):862.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • Between metaphysics and nonsense: Elucidation in Wittgenstein's tractatus.Marie McGinn - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (197):491-513.
    There are currently two readings of Tractatus, the metaphysical and the therapeutic. I argue that neither of these is satisfactory. I develop a third reading, the elucidatory reading. This shares the therapeutic interpretation’s emphasis on the idea that Wittgenstein’s remarks are intended to work on the reader, but instead of seeing these remarks as directed (problematically) at revealing their own nonsensical status, I take the remarks to be aimed at bringing a certain order to the reader’s perception of language. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Reply to John MacFarlane.John Mcdowell - 2004 - Theoria 70 (2-3):266-270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • McDowell’s Kantianism.John Macfarlane - 2004 - Theoria 70 (2-3):250-265.
    In recent work, John McDowell has urged that we resurrect the Kantian thesis that concepts without intuitions are empty. I distinguish two forms of the thesis: a strong form that applies to all concepts and a weak form that is limited to empirical concepts. Because McDowell rejects Kant’s philosophy of mathematics, he can accept only the weaker form of the thesis. But this position is unstable. The reasoning behind McDowell’s insistence that empirical concepts can have content only if they are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Frege, Kant, and the logic in logicism.John MacFarlane - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (1):25-65.
    Let me start with a well-known story. Kant held that logic and conceptual analysis alone cannot account for our knowledge of arithmetic: “however we might turn and twist our concepts, we could never, by the mere analysis of them, and without the aid of intuition, discover what is the sum [7+5]” (KrV, B16). Frege took himself to have shown that Kant was wrong about this. According to Frege’s logicist thesis, every arithmetical concept can be defined in purely logical terms, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • Russell's Hidden Substitutional Theory. [REVIEW]James Levine - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (1):138-141.
    In his 1903 Principles of Mathematics, Russell holds that “it is a characteristic of the terms of a proposition”—that is, its “logical subjects”—“that any one of them may be replaced by any other entity without our ceasing to have a proposition”. Hence, in PoM, Russell holds that from the proposition ‘Socrates is human’, we can obtain the propositions ‘Humanity is human’ and ‘The class of humans is human’, replacing Socrates by the property of humanity and the class of humans, respectively. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Analysis and decomposition in Frege and Russell.James Levine - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (207):195-216.
    Michael Dummett has long argued that Frege is committed to recognizing a distinction between two sorts of analysis of propositional contents: 'analysis', which reveals the entities that one must grasp in order to apprehend a given propositional content; and 'decomposition', which is used in recognizing the validity of certain inferences. Whereas any propositional content admits of a unique ultimate 'analysis' into simple constituents, it also admits of distinct 'decompositions', no one of which is ultimately privileged over the others. I argue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Carnap’s dream: Gödel, Wittgenstein, and Logical, Syntax.S. Awodey & A. W. Carus - 2007 - Synthese 159 (1):23-45.
    In Carnap’s autobiography, he tells the story how one night in January 1931, “the whole theory of language structure” in all its ramifications “came to [him] like a vision”. The shorthand manuscript he produced immediately thereafter, he says, “was the first version” of Logical Syntax of Language. This document, which has never been examined since Carnap’s death, turns out not to resemble Logical Syntax at all, at least on the surface. Wherein, then, did the momentous insight of 21 January 1931 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Naming and Necessity.Saul Kripke - 1980 - Critica 17 (49):69-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1663 citations  
  • Kant and the foundations of mathematics.Philip Kitcher - 1975 - Philosophical Review 84 (1):23-50.
    T HE heart of Kant's views on the nature of mathematics is his thesis that the judgments of pure mathematics are synthetic a priori. Kant usually offers this as one thesis, but it is fruitful to regard it as consisting of two separate claims, a meta- physical subthesis and an epistemological ..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Selected Works of Giuseppe Peano.Hubert C. Kennedy & Giuseppe Peano - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (1):177-180.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Critique of Pure Reason.Wolfgang Schwarz - 1966 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 26 (3):449-451.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   678 citations  
  • Russell, idealism, and the emergence of analytic philosophy.Peter Hylton - 1990 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Analytic philosophy has become the dominant philosophical tradition in the English-speaking world. This book illuminates that tradition through a historical examination of a crucial period in its formation: the rejection of Idealism by Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore at the beginning of the twentieth century, and the subsequent development of Russell's thought in the period before the First World War.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  • Mind and World.Huw Price & John McDowell - 1994 - Philosophical Books 38 (3):169-181.
    How do rational minds make contact with the world? The empiricist tradition sees a gap between mind and world, and takes sensory experience, fallible as it is, to provide our only bridge across that gap. In its crudest form, for example, the traditional idea is that our minds consult an inner realm of sensory experience, which provides us with evidence about the nature of external reality. Notoriously, however, it turns out to be far from clear that there is any viable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1021 citations  
  • Intuition, synthesis, and individuation in the critique of pure reason.Robert Howell - 1973 - Noûs 7 (3):207-232.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations